Friday, February 8, 2019

Centinel I, Part II: Perplexed and Divided

            It likely cannot be said beyond a shadow of a doubt precisely what motivated Samuel Bryan in 1787 to set out his views upon the proposed federal constitution in a series of essays made available to the public. Why did he feel the need to put his words into print? To whom did he believe he was addressing himself? How did he rate his odds of success? For better or worse, these are not questions to which the historical record provides an answer. As to the nature of his concern, however – the quality possessed by the document in question which he believed represented a potential danger to American liberty – Bryan was good enough to provide a fairly forthright answer in the first paragraph of the first entry in what would become a series of publications under the penname of Centinel. With the intention of putting his fellow Pennsylvanians in mind of, “Certain liberties and privileges secured to you by the constitution of this commonwealth,” he accordingly affirmed that,

As yet you have the right to freedom of speech, and of publishing your sentiments. How long those rights will appertain to you, you yourselves are called upon to say, whether your houses shall continue to be your castles; whether your papers, your persons and your property, are to be held sacred and free from general warrants, you are now to determine.

Bryan, it seemed, was mortally concerned that the people of the Keystone State, in spite of successfully claiming and asserting their rights via the adoption of a republican constitution only eleven years prior in 1776, might already have begun to take those same rights for granted. Recognize what you are being asked to give up, he implored them, and do not act with undue haste. That he felt the citizens of Pennsylvania were being asked to give up anything at all naturally forms the crux of his perspective upon both the proposed constitution and political power more generally.

            Had Bryan restricted the treatise which followed to an exploration of the many dangers posed by a powerful, activist government – such as that described by the proposed constitution –  which lacked an accompanying declaration of rights, Centinel I might fairly have been described as making a very sensible – if rather uninteresting – case. Nearly every state constitution then in force contained an explicit enumeration of the various fundamental liberties possessed by the inhabitants of the same. Doubtless this was largely in recognition of the supreme legal and cultural importance attached to the Bill of Rights (1689) within the British libertarian tradition from which the supporters of the American Revolution derived so much. In light of the degree to which that same conflict – only recently settled – had arisen as a result of disagreements over the nature and validity of tradition, precedent, and “common sense,” explicitly codified rights were bound to become an exceptionally important aspect of whatever governments the victorious revolutionaries chose to erect. That the proposed federal constitution made no mention at all of what, if any, civil liberties the resulting government would be inclined to recognize was accordingly the cause of much alarm among a significant portion of the contemporary American public.

Combined with the proposed constitution’s paramount legal status, implied by the text of Article VI – “This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof […] shall be the supreme Law of the Land” – it doubtless seemed as though there would be nothing to prevent the proposed national government from wholly disregarding both the natural rights presumed to be possessed by every citizen of the United States – life, liberty, property, etc. – as well as those explicitly guaranteed by the various state constitutions – freedom from unnecessary search and seizure, freedom of the press, and freedom of assembly, to name but a few. In light of the alarming vulnerability to which the ratification of the proposed constitution seemed prepared to expose the American people, many of the critics of that selfsame document accordingly took it upon themselves either to advocate for its defeat or to convince their fellow citizens to trade their affirmative vote only for the addition of a federal bill of rights. Many of the Anti-Federalist essays subsequently published during the ratification debate (September 28, 1787 – July 26, 1788) made exactly this case. The evident result was that demands for a federal enumeration of rights became the single-most significant hurdle pro-constitution forces were obliged to overcome at a number of the ratifying conventions held in the various states.

Though Samuel Bryan was most certainly also of the opinion that the absence of a declaration of rights within the proposed federal constitution represented a tremendous threat to the fundamental liberties of the American people, this did not form the core of his argument against ratification in Centinel I. Whereas the promise of a federal bill of rights did ultimately allay the concerns of enough delegates at key state conventions to secure the successful ratification of the proposed constitution, the nature of Bryan’s misgivings more or less ensured that they could not have been so easily dispelled. The issue which he took with the theoretical government in question – and which he expressed in the pages of Centinel I – was that it could not possibly have functioned as effectively as its supporters declared it would without eventually succumbing to corruption and despotism. It was not a matter of its simply lacking a few explicit guarantees. On the contrary, it was a question of structure and size, accessibility and oversight. As described in the text of the proposed constitution, Bryan asserted that the national government of the United States of America would be too large, too distant, too powerful, and too complex to perform the basic functions its framers had assigned to it while also respecting the rights and liberties of the people it was intended to serve.

Much of the rationale Bryan deployed to this end in the text of Centinel I could more or less be summed up by the axiom that the best form of government is that which is the easiest for the governed to understand. By Bryan’s reckoning, to “understand” a government would seem to have included both comprehending its function and being able to monitor the same. Speaking to the former, the ninth paragraph Centinel I avowed that,

The great body of the people never steadily attend to the operations of government, and for want of due information are liable to be imposed on-If you complicate the plan by various orders, the people will be perplexed and divided in their sentiments about the sources of abuses or misconduct, some will impute it to the senate, others to the house of representatives, and so on, that the interposition of the people may be rendered imperfect or perhaps wholly abortive.

While the outcome which Bryan appeared to seek certainly aligns with what we’ve since come to think of as small-government conservatism – i.e. public institutions that are rendered more efficient and transparent by being limited in size and power – his stated rationale was arguably much more cynical than that of the average latter-day conservative partisan. The modern advocates of de-regulation, fiscal responsibility, and low taxes tend to couch their priorities within an expressed belief in the ability of the individual to substantially govern themselves – in terms, say, of how they spend their money, make use of their property, or behave towards their neighbors. People, they thereby affirm, are perfectly capable of making sound decisions and living good, productive lives without government constraining their choices or re-distributing whatever wealth they possess. Notwithstanding the somewhat more proscriptive dogmas of social conservatism, this kind of thinking would seem to embody a fairly optimistic view of human nature, wherein it is held that the best qualities of every person should be given the proper space for expression by limiting government interference in their lives.

            Whatever else Samuel Bryan felt about his fellow Americans in terms of their moral or spiritual character, the passage cited above at the very least indicates that he harbored a somewhat less than charitable opinion of their collective intellectual acuity. Either that, or he thought them so prone to laziness that they would inevitably and consistently fail to make the necessary effort to understand how their government functioned if that government was overly complex. Unflattering as this might seem, the aforementioned text appears to be fairly unequivocal. “If you complicate the plan by various orders,” he avowed, “The people will be perplexed and divided in their sentiments about the source of abuses and misconduct [.]” To use an analogy, Bryan might as well have said that if you make a machine which you think is useful and which every person would benefit from possessing too difficult to understand, people will inevitably fail to learn how it works due to some combination of confusion and apathy and thus fail to benefit from whatever boons it has to offer. Upon reflection, this would seem to be almost exactly the kind of advice a veteran designer of appliances, public spaces, or automobiles would surely be given to impart to an up-and-coming apprentice. If there is a chance that people will become confused by something you have built, they might well say, you should count on that chance cropping up nine times out of ten. The solution is to make the things that people are going to interact with on a daily basis as simple and as intuitive as possible. Someone should know how something works just by looking at it, and should never be left scratching their head if that something happens to go wrong.

            It would be difficult to deny that this constitutes very sound advice. It most certainly does. It just isn’t the kind of counsel one tends to hear within the public realm of democratic government. Doubtless, as long as public opinion has been a factor in how a given state is administered there have been discussions in backrooms and smoky parlors about the credulity and the idleness of the common man, his inability to comprehend the great matters of state, and the need for sound guidance and decisive leadership in the highest echelons of power. But rarely do those who, in order to succeed, must sway the public to their point of view speak of such things in a open forum. That Samuel Bryan appeared to do so – in the form of the cited passage of Centinel I – would therefore seem a curious thing indeed. Granted, there were other principles which he felt inclined to uphold, and against which he seemed to think that the proposed constitution stood to act. Recall, to that end, the exhortation he rendered unto his countrymen in Pennsylvania that their continued ability to exercise freedom of speech, freedom of the press, and the sovereignty of their persons and property had been placed entirely in their hands by the possibility of their agreeing to ratify the proposed federal charter. Clearly, he feared for this loss of fundamental liberties. It would, in consequence, seem reasonable to conclude that he did not oppose the adoption of the United States Constitution solely because he thought that the national government created as a result would be too complicated for most people to wrap their heads around. That being said, it was the latter justification he spend the better part of a paragraph explaining, and upon which seemed to hang the general thesis of Centinel I.

            The thrust of that thesis appeared to be, in essence, that the framework of government described by the proposed constitution simply wasn’t practical. There were certainly ideological roots to this conviction, not the least of which was Bryan’s avowed belief that what was at stake in America as 1787 turned to 1788 was nothing less than, “All the blessings of liberty and the dearest privileges of freemen [.]” But the general mode of expression in Centinel I – the means by which Bryan sought to justify his various criticisms of the United States Constitution – were of an almost uniformly pragmatic character. Consider, on that head, the description he offered of what an ideal government ought to look like. “Vest all the legislative power in one body of men,” he avowed,

Elected for a short period, and necessarily excluded by rotation from permanency, and guarded from precipitancy and surprise by delays imposed on its proceedings, you will create the most perfect responsibility for then, whenever the people feel a grievance they cannot mistake the authors, and will apply the remedy with certainty and effect, discarding them at the next election.

To his belief that people needed to freely comprehend the government under which their lived, Bryan thus joined the principle of day-to-day transparency and accountability. This would seem to constitute the other dimension of political understanding which he appeared so keen to promote. A government whose function is obvious, after all, and whose various mechanisms remain open to scrutiny not only promotes public trust and engagement. It also ensures that those responsible for error – or worse – cannot simply disappear into a byzantine network of bureaucrats, committees, and departments so as to avoid taking responsibility for their

The organizational framework described by the proposed constitution doubtless appeared specifically constructed to project just this kind of administrative smokescreen. Between a House of Representatives, a Senate, an independent executive branch, and all such offices as it would devolve upon any one of these bodies to fill by appointment, what hope might the average person have harbored of tracing the cause of a particularly injurious policy to its source, let alone of exercising the requisite oversight? A petitioner might make their case to a Representative, who might in turn point to a Senator, who then claims that responsibility lies with the executive branch, which might indicate, when prompted, that the blame should in truth be leveled at a given semi-independent department. And what was then to stop the head of that selfsame department, upon being questioned, from pointing to the legislative committee whose members authorized and funded the offending policy to begin with? Within a system of such manifest complexity, the various branches of which were purposefully intertwined as a means of creating a nominally stable balance of power, mere comprehension would seem to convey only a partial advantage. In order for the governed to truly be secure in the enjoyment of their liberties, they must be able to identify the author of a given measure with ease, entertain a reasonable expectation of that author taking receipt of their responsibility, and possess the means of replacing those who fail to take heed when their performance is thus called into question. 

No comments:

Post a Comment