Friday, February 22, 2019

Centinel I, Part IV: So Great a Country

            The degree to which Samuel Bryan believed that simplicity was an absolutely essentially element of any government intended to remain apart from despotism, tyranny, and corruption – and the extent to which he was convinced that this need for simplicity was grounded upon a very practical course of reasoning – was made exceptionally clear in paragraphs seventeen, eighteen, and nineteen of Centinel I, all of which sought to address the evident inadequacy of the “extended republic” which the advocates of a more centralized national government tacitly endorsed. The issue at hand was essentially one of size. In addition to taking issue with certain aspects of the structure of government proposed by the United States Constitution, it seemed, Bryan was also highly suspicious of the scale of the undertaking and its effect upon the end result. How could any government, he seemed inclined to ask, intended to exert its authority over the United States of America in such granular areas as taxation, commerce, monetary policy, and criminal justice possibly do so in a manner that didn’t prejudice the needs of certain communities over those of others? Notwithstanding the immense diversity of interests which the various states collectively represented – from plantation agriculture, to mining, to industry, shipping, shipbuilding, and banking – the tremendous physical distances between America’s major population centers, state capitals, and the national capital – at that point, in October of 1787, New York City – presented a host of seemingly insurmountable logistical challenges which Bryan appeared unconvinced that the proposed constitution had adequately addressed. How, in attempting to make law for – and, perhaps more pressingly, lay taxes upon – an otherwise fairly loose agglomeration of communities whose daily lived experiences and practical concerns were not particularly alike, could any government forced to operate at often very significant distances from its constituents possibly create and implement policies that adequately served their needs?

            In attempting to answer this question, Bryan delved for perhaps the only time across the length of Centinel I into the realm of political theory. As it happened, the ability of a large swath of territory to be successfully governed as a republic had been discussed to significant effect by no less august a personage in the realm of Western philosophy than that estimable architect of the theory of separation of powers in government, Charles-Louis de Secondat, Baron de La Brède et de Montesquieu (1689-1755). In his highly influential tract, The Spirit of the Laws (1748) – discussed here previously on more than one occasion – Montesquieu made specific mention, within the context of a larger discussion about the unique qualities of various kinds of governments, of what he believed to be the ideal relationship between the republican form of administration and the physical dimensions of the region to be administered. A stable republic on a large scale was essentially impossible, the great philosophe affirmed, because the mechanism upon which the republican model depends in order to function – i.e. the distillation and implementation of public opinion – worked best in conditions that favored a clear consensus of thought and action. “In a large republic,” he thereby asserted,

The public good is sacrificed to a thousand views; it is subordinate to exceptions; and depends on accidents. In a small one, the interest of the public is easier perceived, better understood, and more within the reach of every citizen; abuses have a less extent, and of course are less protected.

The phenomenon which Montesquieu had evidently observed was that it tends to be harder to form an actionable consensus as the number and diversity of opinions involved increases. A group of five people, for example, can almost certainly decide where they’re going to have lunch much more quickly and easily than a group of fifty, or five hundred, or five thousand. As this tendency applied to the business of republican government, it had evidently struck the author of The Spirit of the Laws that the greater the number of people directly involved in seeking out and pursuing the public good, the less likely it became that the public good would ever actually be served. Though Montesquieu did not provide a detailed explanation as to how and why this would be the case, a moment’s thought would seem to affirm the essential logic of his contention.

            Consider, to that end, the topic of trade. In a small republic whose economy is completely and uniformly dominated by agriculture, policy discussions would almost certainly be ruled by the underlying consensus that securing access to viable export markets for the produce of the nation must be among the first priorities of government. Doubtless there would be some objection to this among whatever urban artisans or manufacturers reside within the republic in question. Those seeking to establish a local market for their goods must needs oppose the freedom of trade – and the accompanying lack of economic protections – sought by their agriculturalist neighbors. But the overriding lack of economic diversity essentially guaranteed by the small size of the relevant polity would more or less ensure that such complaints never rise to the level of threatening the aforementioned political consensus. If that same republic were to grow, however, by steadily encompassing territories whose climate, natural resources, or geo-physical situation inclined them towards different kinds of industries than were theretofore possible under the flag of their newfound government, the result must inevitably be the splintering of public opinion and the breakdown of the accustomed consensus. Now possessed of a substantial mining sector, say, as well as an even larger manufacturing sector, it could no longer be taken as a given that the various individuals chosen to sit in the national assembly of the republic could and would arrive at a speedy and effective definition of the public good. With agriculture now possessing a much decreased economic significance, and mining and manufacturing competing for the position of rising industrial concern, compromise becomes essential for any progress to be made at all. While this is not in itself a crippling condition, the end result would almost certainly be as Montesquieu described it. The public good, once quite narrowly defined and easily implemented, becomes “subordinate to exceptions,” takes on a vaguer and more generic character, and no longer serves to benefit quite as deeply as it once did.  

            Samuel Bryan’s description of essentially this same phenomenon in the aforementioned passages of Centinel I are what arguably attest to his familiarity with its terms. Indeed, he affirmed explicitly in paragraph seventeen that,

It is the opinion of the greatest writers, that a very extensive country cannot be governed on democratical principles, on any other plan, than a confederation of a number of smaller republics, possessing all the powers of internal government, but united in the management of their foreign and general affairs.

While this is not Montesquieu exactly, the influence of that earlier writer’s ideas upon the general contours of Bryan’s expressed opinion would seem clear enough. This becomes yet more obvious when one considers his further comment in paragraph nineteen of Centinel I that,

If one general government could be instituted and maintained on principles of freedom, it would not be so competent to attend to the various local concerns and wants, of every particular district, as well as the peculiar governments, who are nearer the scene, and possessed of superior means of information [.]

Granted, Bryan and Montesquieu did appear to come at the same issue from slightly different angles. Montesquieu believed that the inability of republican government to function adequately on a large scale stemmed from the difficulty that must ever arise from distilling many and diverse opinions into useful policy. The greater the number of views that must be taken into account, he asserted, the harder it becomes to locate and act on the public good. Bryan, by comparison, seemed to be concerned more with the physical ungainliness of a large republic than its tendency to govern in terms of poorly-defined generalities.

            Speaking specifically of the United States of America as it existed in 1787 – a union of thirteen states stretching some fifteen hundred miles north to south – Samuel Bryan avowed that whatever government could possibly administer the whole of its extensive territory without succumbing to despotism would inevitably struggle to do so in a particularly effective manner. “The various local concerns and wants, of every particular district” would surely be beyond the abilities of a general government to acknowledge, let alone attend to, rendering whatever directives said government ultimately attempted to pursue of limited use to the general population. Indeed, limited knowledge of the specific practices of diverse and distant regions might even produce policies which benefit the bare majority of the American people while harming a still sizable minority of the same. Local governments, Bryan asserted, “who are nearer the scene, and possessed of superior means of information” are preferable for exactly this reason. Capable of comprehending the needs and concerns of the communities under their auspices far more accurately than an authority located some distance away and burdened with a much wider scope of responsibility, such small, limited governments were likewise bound to be more attentive to the needs of their constituents and more adept at responding in an effective and timely manner.

            Notwithstanding this evident difference in focus, Bryan most definitely agreed with Montesquieu’s basic contention that the larger a republic grew physically, the less competent it became at serving the needs of its citizens. Granted, this was a broadly theoretical contention. As the examples put forward in the relevant passage of The Spirit of the Laws attest, there weren’t many historical examples of republican government on any scale to draw upon whilst arguing for or against the supposed benefits and flaws of that selfsame model. Montesquieu made explicit mention of one of them – that of the ancient Greek city-state republics – by way of affirming that the limited republic was uniquely possessed of political stability. “It was the spirit of the Greek republics [,]” he accordingly declared, “To be as contented with their territories, as with their laws […] All was lost upon the starting up of monarchy, a government whose spirit is more turned to increase and advancement.” Ambition, it seemed, was the great corrupting vice of republicanism, for it must ever have led to conquest, expansion, diffusion, and weakness. A small republic was strong, Montesquieu was keen to point out, because its government possessed the confidence of the greatest number of its inhabitants. And a large republic was weak because the confidence of its people became so difficult to define as to render government either ineffective or – more worryingly – a thing apart.

            The other primary example of historical republicanism which Montesquieu and Bryan alike could have drawn upon – but which neither The Spirit of the Laws or Centinel I did with much effect – would seem to speak to exactly this latter tendency. The Roman Republic, though for many Enlightenment thinkers a beacon of virtuous and balanced self-government, also rather paradoxically stands as one of the foremost examples of how susceptible republicanism can be to political corruption and institutional atrophy. Notwithstanding the exceptionally rigorous limitations placed upon the various political officials who served Rome – term limits, frequent elections, age qualifications, etc. – the profusion of assemblies responsible for various aspects of public administration, and the checks and balances put in place amongst the multifarious organs of government, the Roman Republic still eventually succumbed to its own worst aspects. Lust for territory led to expansion, which in turn brought about a diffusion of political authority, the empowerment of ambitious military figures, the erosion of political norms, and the triumph of demagoguery, populism, and tyranny. From a city-state interested in little more than protecting its own sovereignty and seeing to the needs of its inhabitants, Rome was transformed over the course of four centuries and innumerable wars into an extensive empire whose population, military, and government either tended to work at cross purposes or possessed very different priorities.

The application of this regrettable outcome to the circumstances of late 18th century America would seem obvious enough. If one of the only reasonably successful republics ever to exist was eventually transformed into a despotic empire as a direct result of its tendency towards territorial expansion, perhaps it was wise to think very carefully about any project which seemed to have the same object in mind. The United States Constitution, of course, did not describe a polity which much resembled ancient Rome, institutionally or structurally. But the republic it did frame embraced a scale and centralization of authority that was to some extent imperial in nature, and this in itself entailed certain fundamental risks. While the United States of America certainly enjoyed the benefit of strong sub-national governments – in the form of the states – which could stand in opposition to the federal government if or when it appeared to exceed its stated mandate, the power possessed by the latter was still substantial, and the distance between the seat of national power and the “provinces” was at times quite large. Bearing this in mind, what was there to prevent the United States government from acting against the interests of a state – or states – located at the far edge of its nominal authority? Being responsible for such a vast and diverse swath of territory, why should this same government not simply ignore all but the most basic needs of the communities under its auspices? Montesquieu had predicted an answer in the negative – i.e. “The public good is sacrificed to a thousand views” – and even a cursory glance at the extant history of republican government would arguably have affirmed the wisdom of his case.    

But most of this was, again, theoretical, and perhaps too theoretical for the liking of Samuel Bryan. As the text of Centinel I seems otherwise to demonstrate, the son of George Bryan was possessed of an eminently pragmatic turn of mind. Whereas, for example, certain of his contemporaries claimed that smaller governments were preferable to larger ones because the former did not threaten so much as the latter to encroach upon the liberties of the individual, Bryan – without necessarily disagreeing with this contention – avowed that simple governments were preferable because people were more likely to adequately scrutinize something they could actually understand. Just so, the aforementioned argument which Bryan offered in Centinel I against the creation of a centralized national government in the United States of America was accompanied by a decidedly practical rationale. “Do we not already see,” he thus avowed,

That the inhabitants in a number of larger states, who are remote from the seat of government, are loudly complaining of the inconveniences and disadvantages they are subjected to on this account, and that, to enjoy the comforts of local government, they are separating into smaller divisions.

In addition to pointing to the lived experience of some portion of his fellow Americans for validation rather than to the sometimes abstract ruminations of European philosophy, this assertion on the part of Bryan also had the advantage of being quite easy to verify.

No comments:

Post a Comment