Friday, December 28, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part XIX: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain, contd.

As with his citation of the Dutch Revolt in Part II, Section IV of Observations, Price’s subsequent invocation of certain episodes from classical antiquity present a similarly awkward attempt to find broad – and rhetorically useful – parallels between the circumstances of British policy in late 18th century America and specific incidents in European history. The first of these, offered in brief at the end of an already fairly succinct paragraph, took the form of an exhortation on the part of Price to his prospective audience. “Let any one read also,” he avowed,

The history of the war which the Athenians, from a thirst of Empire, made on the Syracusans of Sicily, a people derived from the same origin with them; and let him, if he can, avoid rejoicing in the defeat of the Athenians.

The event being here referred to is the Sicilian Expedition (415-413 BC), one of the final campaigns of the decades-long Peloponnesian War (431-404 BC) between the respective alliances of regional hegemons Athens and Sparta. While Price seemed intent on presenting the incident as another tragic example of a thirst for empire bringing about one people’s unpardonable abuse of their own relations, however, the actual circumstances were nowhere near so cut and dried.

The people of Syracuse, for example, though most definitely of Greek derivation, were in fact the descendants of settlers from Corinth rather than Athens. As Athens was an Ionian city while Corinth was Dorian – these being two of the four tribes into which the Greek people divided themselves – this meant that the people of Syracuse would have spoken a different language, possessed a different culture, and partook of a substantially separate social identity that their nominal Athenian oppressors. Furthermore, while the Athenian motive for invading Syracuse was inarguably tied to Athens’ desire to cut off a potential source of food and military assistance to its Spartan rival, Syracuse was itself something of a local hegemon whose military and commercial resources had allowed it to effectively control the whole of Sicily. Indeed, the first Athenian expeditions dispatched to the island were sent in response to a plea for assistance from another Sicilian city – Leontinoi – whose inhabitants had been struggling for decades to assert their independence from either Syracuse or one of its rivals. Far from an innocent bystander caught in the crossfire of a power struggle between rival empires, therefore, Syracuse represented a burgeoning empire in its own right whose interests largely paralleled those of the great powers of the ancient Greek world. 

In consequence of these circumstances, it was not the brutality of the Athenian campaign in Syracuse that sent shockwaves through the contemporary Aegean, or any horror which might have resulted from the sight of a powerful empire laying waste to a related people. On the contrary, what observers at the time found most striking was the degree to which Athens endured one reverse after another without retreating, as well as the scale of that city’s ultimate defeat. The expedition itself had in large part been the product of political maneuvering within the Athenian political scene – playing out as a struggle between pro-Spartan advocates of peace and anti-Spartan supporters of continued war – and accordingly progressed in a somewhat haphazard fashion. For example, while initially proposed in response to a plea for assistance from the Sicilian city of Segesta against a local rival, the pro-war faction advocated for Syracuse as the final target of the expedition – seeing as it represented the greater threat to Athenian interests – and succeeded in redirecting its resources over the course of the journey from Greece to Southern Italy. The scale of the endeavor was also the product of political intrigue, stemming from the efforts of pro-peace partisan Nicias (470-413 BC) to dissuade his fellow citizens from partaking in what he regarded as an unnecessary distraction. Stymied by the successful lobbying of pro-war advocate Alcibiades (450-404 BC), Nicias suggested a dramatic increase of the requested ships and men in the hope that the people of Athens would recoil at the thought of committing so many of their precious resources to what was obviously a needless foreign adventure. This tactic unfortunately backfired when, perhaps encouraged by the suddenly unanimous support for the Sicilian excursion, the assembled citizens enthusiastically approved the revised proposal, thus committing some five thousand men and one hundreds ships to the efforts at a time when Athens could ill afford to lose them.

This seeming comedy of errors continued upon the arrival of the assembled forces at Sicily. The three commanders assigned to lead the expedition – Nicias, Alcibiades, and a veteran soldier named Lamachus – frequently disagreed as to the nature and direction of their mission, with Nicias favoring a very limited campaign and Alcibiades and Lamachus arguing for a more expansive foray against the island’s major power centers. This dynamic was quickly interrupted, however, upon the arrest of Alcibiades by an envoy sent from Athens. Ostensibly accused of certain religious offenses – though in fact the victim of further political skullduggery – the primary advocate and architect of the venture was thus sent home almost before it began. He subsequently escaped from confinement, sought refuge in Sparta, and turned over any number of secrets to his former homeland’s hated rival. Accordingly left to command the expedition between them, Nicias and Lamachus then proceeded to lead an unsuccessful first assault on Syracuse, wintered in Southern Italy while awaiting reinforcements, engaged in a campaign of fortification building and blockades the following summer, and entirely failed to petition sufficient local allies for assistance. The death of Lamachus during this phase of the expedition was followed by the arrival of a relief force from Sparta and Corinth – dispatched, it bears noting, on the advice of Alcibiades – the uniting of all previously neutral Sicilian cities under Spartan leadership, a call for reinforcements from Athens – which Nicias hoped would be refused, and which, to his frustration, was not – and a final Athenian attempt to leave the island that was ultimately thwarted by a mixture of superstition and indecisiveness on the part of their commanders. Suffering a final defeat and surrender in 413 BC after having their ships destroyed and being forced to march inland, what remained of the expedition – between the initial force and subsequent reinforcements, some ten thousand men in total – were either executed, sold into slavery, or left to die of starvation and disease as prisoners of Syracuse.

Granting that this series was never intended to devolve into a recitation of ancient battles or an accounting of the political intrigue which characterized the civilizations of Classical Greece, one may rest easy in the knowledge that the details cited above were offered with a very particular purpose in mind. To wit, while Richard Price seemed intent on characterizing the Sicilian Expedition as being substantially in parallel with the North Ministry’s campaign against the Thirteen Colonies – in that they were both conducted by major imperial powers against a related people who were comparatively overmatched – the facts just now related about the former clearly demonstrate that this was not at all the case. Syracuse was not a colony of Athens, the expedition was not undertaken in order to affirm any supposed Athenian right to rule the island of Sicily, the whole excursion was the product of, and subject to, the arbitrary decision-making of a relatively small number on intriguers and partisans, and the final defeat of Athens came in large part at the hands of its perennial rival, Sparta. There was little one could declare to be particularly unjust in Athens’ behavior towards Syracuse, rather much one could comparatively complain of in the Syracusan treatment of the defeated Athenians, and little in the way of substantial moral significance to the prosecution of the affair or its outcome. Nicias, it might be said, badly misjudged the temper of his countrymen, and Alcibiades might conceivably be chided for making too many enemies and for too swiftly turning on his fellow Athenians. It remains, however, something of an open question what any of this has to do with the war being waged at the time of Price’s writing between Great Britain and the American colonies. While the use of an episode from classical antiquity as reminder of where his countrymen’s sympathies ought to have laid may indeed have served his efforts well – particularly in light of the affection with which many members of the contemporary British elite regarded the history and culture of Classical Greece – the events of the Sicilian Expedition were plainly not what Price desired them to be.

Nor, it seemed, were the circumstances of the Social War (91-88 BC) which the author of Observations next proceeded to invoke. “Read the account of the social war among the Romans [,]” he thus declared.

The allied states of Italy had fought the battles of Rome, and contributed by their valor and treasure to its conquests and grandeur. They claimed, therefore, the rights of Roman citizens, and a share with them in legislation. The Romans, disdaining to make those their fellow-citizens, whom they had always looked upon as their subjects, would not comply; and a war followed, which ended in the ruin of the Roman Republic. The feelings of every Briton in this case must force him to approve the conduct of the Allies, and to condemn the proud and ungrateful Romans.

While this account might reasonably be pronounced be as being being broadly correct, it nevertheless fails to accomplish the objective for which Price deployed it for two basic reasons. First – and most glaringly – the Roman Republic was not ruined by the outcome of the Social War. If it had been, the subsequent transformation of said republic into one of the most powerful and most significant empires in the history of human civilization would surely not have occurred. And second, while the Anglo-American crisis concerned the efforts of certain dependent states of a larger empire to assert the primacy of their domestic independence against imperial encroachment, the Social War conversely stemmed from the desire of a collection of subjects peoples to enjoy a greater share of the rewards which resulted from their hegemon’s various imperial forays.

            Consider, by way of explanation, the nature of the Roman Republic just prior to the outbreak of the Social War. While the centuries which followed the founding of the republican phase of the Roman government – generally marked as taking place in 509 BC – witnessed repeated successful campaigns of expansion and conquest in such disparate regions as the Iberian Peninsula, Greece, North Africa, and Anatolia, Italy itself remained under something less than the complete control of the city of Rome well into the 80s BC. Rather than administer the various Italian provinces which fell outside the direct authority of the Senate via a series of appointed governors – as was the case with non-Italian possessions – power had instead been vested in the individual tribal communities that were native to the areas in question. The government of Southern Italy, for example, was left to indigenous peoples like the Samnites and the Lucani, central Abruzzo to the Marrucini, Vestini, and Paeligni, and Umbria to the Marsi. And while the relationships which these people enjoyed with their Roman cousins varied according to whether they had submitted peacefully to the authority of Rome or had been defeated in war, it was standard procedure for all of the local tribes to see to their own domestic needs while leaving foreign policy decisions to the Senate.

Durable though this arrangement proved, certain aspects of it in time became a source of tension and resentment among the various non-Roman peoples involved. None of them, for instance, were granted the privilege of Roman citizenship, though they fought in large numbers in the Roman legions of the day. Indeed, by the 2nd century BC, Rome’s Italian “allies” contributed between one half and two-thirds of the Roman field army, and were simultaneously subject to taxation in the form of annual tribute. In spite of having contributed their blood and treasure to Rome’s expansion, however, their collective disenfranchisement ensured that they would never enjoy the fruits of their efforts. Conquered land, held in public trust by the government of the republic, was more often than not doled out to wealthy Roman landowners rather than to those who had helped capture and secure it. In consequence, while certain Romans became richer as the republic expanded, the people doing the actual expanding received hardly anything for their trouble. And though, at the same time, though they remained generally unmolested in their home regions, the Samnites, Marsi, and Vestini were forced by their lack of standing within Rome’s domestic political scene to render up their fighting men whenever they were called upon to do so. Lacking citizenship, they had no place in Rome’s various tribal assemblies, no influence over the elections of its magistrates, and no voice in the Senate during discussion upon war and peace.

Marcus Livius Drusus (130-91 BC), a reformist Tribune of the Plebs – i.e. the elected representative of the common people of Rome – attempted to alter this unequivocally imbalanced state of affairs when he proposed legislation in 91 BC which would have extended Roman citizenship to all of Rome’s Italian allies. Having come to depend on the manpower that these various subject peoples provided, it doubtless appeared to him both good form and good sense to take such measure as would ensure that they had no cause to become unnecessarily disgruntled.  Having already aggravated the traditionalist element of the Roman elite with his incessant politicking over the course of the previous year, however, the proposal was rejected by the enemies of Drusus in the Senate – many of whom also feared the power he would accrue from instantly enfranchising entire communities of potential supporters – and he was subsequently assassinated near the end of his year in office under circumstances which still remain mysterious. Their nearest chance at political empowerment now dashed, the supporters of reform among the Italian peoples almost immediately raised the banner of rebellion. In the conflict that followed, the Italians and Romans alike raised over one hundred thousand men and suffered some fifty thousand casualties each. Despite a series of early defeats – and the death of one of its Consuls – Rome managed to endure the resulting onslaught long enough to carve out a victory for itself by the dawning of 88 BC. At this point, having perhaps absorbed the lesson embedded in Drusus’ support for citizenship reform, the Senate managed to see its way clear to passing a pair of laws intended to both end the Roman-Italian conflict and prevent its future recurrence. The first, approved in 90 BC, was the Lex Julia de Civitate Latinis et Socii Danda, the terms of which extended Roman citizenship to all Italian peoples who had not taken up arms in revolt. This measure was followed in 89 BC by the Lex Plautia Papiria de Civitate Sociis Danda, which further extended the franchise to those Italians tribes who had declared themselves independent two years prior. The Social War – so named after the Italian allies, or socii – came to an end shortly thereafter with the defeat of the inveterate Samnites and the restoration of peace in Italy.

Once again, in light of all that has just been cited, consider the degree to which the circumstances of the Social War compare to those of the Anglo-American crisis and the subsequent armed conflict. The allies were not colonists of Rome who had been planted in the various regions of Italy with the intention of extracting local resources and/or provided markets for Roman manufacturing. Indeed, this might rather be taken to describe the relationship between republican Rome and its various non-Italian provinces, the purpose of which was generally to secure the Roman homeland from attack while providing much needed commodities like grain and iron. Price’s focus was not on Rome’s somewhat dictatorial rule over its extended empire, however, but on its relationship with the Socii, none of whom were of Roman derivation. In consequence, it would also seem fair to conclude that the Social War did not constitute an attempt by a given authority to abrogate the rights or appropriate the wealth of a related people. On the contrary, the issue at the heart of the conflict was that the Italians had no rights within Roman society. It was not the violation of their liberties that prompted them to revolt, therefore, but the fact that their longstanding contribution to Rome’s imperial expansion had yet to be substantially recognized. The Italians, in short, did not simply want to be left to their own devices. Rather, they sought to partake of – and perhaps to some degree direct – the conquests of which their fighting men formed a central component.

Consequent to the above, Price’s affirmations that Rome was ruined by the outcome of the Social War, and that every one of his countrymen would doubtless sympathize with the Italian allies and condemn the Romans, should appear exceptionally curious. What, in truth, had either of these points got to do with the actions of the North Ministry against the Thirteen Colonies? Rome was not ruined by the Social War. Indeed, as of 88 BC, the Romans had barely begun the historic chain of conquests which would ultimately render them the most powerful empire in the known world. And what if the British people did sympathize with the allies? Given though they may have been to identify the glory of their own expansive domain with that of Augustus (63 BC–14 AD) and his successors, there was no reason certain of them wouldn’t be given to compassion when asked to consider the plight of a people so completely subjugated in their foreign affairs to the discretion of an authority they could not themselves control. What of it? The American colonists were fully subjects of the British Crown, protected by their charters and by the terms of the Bill of Rights. Far from contributing to an empire in which they had no share, they benefited greatly from access to markets for their produce, from military and diplomatic protection, and from the ability to purchase some of the finest manufactured goods then available in the world. How, in light of all this, could they possibly compare to the benighted Socii?

Granted, the colonists and the Italian allies alike suffered to have their fates in some part decided by a government in which they had no part. But there the similarity between them substantially ends. Notwithstanding Price’s implication to the contrary, the behavior of the North Ministry towards the Thirteen Colonies did not much resemble the relationship between the Roman Republic and the various Italian client tribes tied to it by treaty. Apart from the conflicts which arose surrounding attempts made to curtail colonial expansion into territories ostensibly set aside for Britain’s Native American allies – a noteworthy but ultimately secondary source of tension within the Anglo-American relationship – the American colonists showed no outward interest in the 1760s and 1770s in receiving a greater share of the spoils of Britain’s continued global expansion. Unlike the Socii, they were not called upon to serve in British campaigns outside of their native environs – in India, say, or Africa, or Europe – and thus had no reason to either expect compensation for the foreign service they had rendered or to be concerned about how they were going to next be put to use. When Americans fought under the British banner, they fought in America, for the purpose – directly or indirectly – of protecting their homes. What concerned them, then, rather than any lack of compensation or consent in the realm of military affairs, was the sanctity of the liberties to which they believed their citizenship and their governing charters entitled them.

The Socii, by comparison, seemed to nurture far more martial intentions. Their primary interaction with Rome was in the realm of military service, and it was through that service that they sought to assert themselves politically. This, in essence, is what the Social War was all about. Having failed to carve out a space for themselves within Rome’s burgeoning empire by taking up arms on behalf of that selfsame republic, the Italian peoples instead sought to achieve the same objective by turning their swords upon their former masters. Noble though such an effort may seem, however – and though Price endeavored to make it appear – subsequent events within the history of the Roman Republic arguably cast some doubt upon the righteousness thereof. Having secured, at great cost, the right to share in the planning and outcome of Rome’s expansionist conflicts, the same Samnites, Marsi, and Lucani with whom Price implored his readers to sympathize proceeded in the centuries that followed to conquer half the world alongside their fellow Roman citizens. Far from endeavoring to seek a voice in Roman politics for the purpose of promoting peace, they instead seemed only desirous of waging war on more favorable terms. One naturally struggles to maintain a degree of sympathy when liberty, hard won, is turned to such ignominious purposes. Price having earlier condemned the Roman Republic for the tyrannical way it governed its provinces in part I, Section III of Observations, he would surely have been of this same sentiment himself. That he appeared to have forgotten the role which the various tribes of Socii must have played in securing these provinces to Roman control would therefore seem to represent either a lapse in memory on his part or an unfortunate side-effect of a particular rhetorical conviction. 

Friday, December 21, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part XVIII: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain, contd.

The next example Price offered in Part II, Section IV of his Observations, while delving further back into European history, adopted essentially this same approach as his analysis of the Corsican Crisis. The colonies, in this case, were represented by the provinces of the Netherlands which would go on to form the Dutch Republic at the end of the 16th century, with Britain’s equivalent accordingly being the Kingdom of Spain as ruled by the House of Hapsburg. “The United Provinces of Holland [,]” Price accordingly explained,

Were once subject to the Spanish monarchy; but, provoked by the violation of their charters, by levies of money, without their consent; by the introduction of Spanish troops among them by innovations in their antient modes of government; and the rejection of their petitions, they were driven to that resistance which we and all the world have since admired; and which has given birth to one of the greatest and happiest Republics that ever existed.

While, somewhat curiously, nothing more than this was offered in the aforementioned passage of Observations, the thrust of Price’s intention would nevertheless seem fairly evident. Spain, he endeavored to remind his audience, had brought about the loss of its territories in the Netherlands by precisely the kind of overestimation of its authority that Britain had itself arguably committed in relation to the Thirteen Colonies. Doubtless seeking to drive this point home further, the offences cited by Price as having been committed by the Spanish against the inhabitants of the Netherlands very closely aligned with those the North Ministry had been lately accused of in America. Spain – like Britain, it seemed – had provoked rebellion in one of its dependent populations by, “The violation of their charters, by levies of money, without their consent; by the introduction of […] troops among them by innovations in their antient modes of government; and [by] the rejection of their petitions [.]” If it could be agreed, then, that the subsequent revolt and independence of the United Provinces of the Netherlands was wholly justified by these abuses – an opinion which Price most certainly held, and which he seemed willing to attribute to the majority of his countrymen –it seemingly followed that the North Ministry’s parallel policies in America likewise provided ample justification for colonial resistance.

            As with his previous citation of the Corsican Crisis, however, Price’s treatment of the Dutch War of Independence was somewhat lacking in nuance. His citation of the “charters” of the Dutch provinces as having been violated by the Spanish monarchy, for example, somewhat misconstrues the nature and character of the contemporary Spanish Netherlands. Unlike the American colonies to which they were being directly compared, the various counties and duchies which collectively comprised the “Low Countries” were not the product of communal/imperial efforts at exploration, expansion, or commerce. The County of Flanders, for example, was not founded by Spanish settlers in cooperation with royal authorities or with the aid of private capital. Rather, the provinces of the Netherlands were separate feudal possessions which over time were successively inherited by the Dukes of Burgundy (1384), the Archdukes of Austria (1482), and the Kings of Spain (1556). Throughout these periodic transfers of sovereignty, the individual lordships, manors, towns, and church holdings within the provinces began to normalize certain procedures, affirm precedents within the context of their various feudal relationships, and delineate specific privileges as having become, by custom, effectively inviolable. Attempts by Burgundian and Hapsburg authorities to abrogate or elide the primacy of these traditional forms – generally in pursuit of a more centralized model of administration on the model of contemporary France – frequently met with armed resistance, notably culminating in the granting by Duchess Mary (1457-1482) to the States General – a kind of representative assembly of the various provincial authorities – of the so-called “Great Privilege” in 1477. While this guarantee was shortly thereafter abrogated by Mary’s husband, Maximilian of Austria (1459-1519), the memory of its existence arguably served as a kind of rallying point for subsequent revolts against Hapsburg rule.

            By the time the Dutch Revolt began at the end of the 1560s, the formal administration of the Netherlands could thus hardly have been described as streamlined, rational, or harmonious. Indeed, it rather represented something of a patchwork of local, regional, and imperial authorities. Power was shared – unevenly, it must be said – amongst municipal governments, the local nobility, provincial governments, imperial officials, the States General, and whatever governor had been appointed by the Spanish Crown. Perhaps unsurprisingly, hardly any of this arrangement was codified, and there remained an underlying tension between the provincial interests of the various local power-brokers and the centralizing ambitions of their nominal Hapsburg rulers. While this latter characteristic could perhaps also be fairly ascribed to the Anglo-American relationship during the majority of the 17th and 18th centuries, the history and dynamics of the English/British colonial project were otherwise wholly unlike those which characterized Hapsburg rule in the Netherlands. Whereas the aforesaid counties and duchies were secured in their privileges by a web of customs, traditions, local and regional institutions, and a continually shifting balance of power – almost none of which, it bears repeating, was codified by law – the various colonies all possessed written charters, granted to them under the authority of the Crown, which clearly defined both the nature and style of their respective governments and the character of their relationship with the relevant imperial authorities. To claim, therefore – as Price seemed intent on doing – that the Dutch provinces suffering to have their “charters” violated by the Spanish Crown was the same as the Thirteen Colonies having their governments violated by the British Crown represents something of an awkward and ultimately flawed comparison.

            There could be no question that Parliament and the Crown had violated the sovereignty of The Province of Massachusetts when, in May, 1774, they respectively approved and gave sanction to an act of law revoking the charter of the same. The very fact of the charter indicated the existence of a compact between two parties – the inhabitants of Massachusetts and the British Crown – which could not be independently abrogated or altered by either, and which gave fairly unequivocal evidence that the sovereignty of the one was fundamentally separate from the sovereignty of the other. Just so, while the governing charters of the other American colonies did not necessarily declare and affirm that the British Parliament could not make laws which acted upon them – in the form of taxation, for example, or commercial regulations – the explicit codification of separate legislative bodies would seem quite clearly to indicate that Parliament was never intended to govern America directly. The actions of the North Ministry – and those of the Grafton, Chatham, Rockingham, and Grenville ministries before them – could therefore reasonably be described as standing in unequivocal opposition to the dictums of a relationship that had theretofore been well and clearly established and attested.

Conversely, the same could almost certainly not be said of the actions of the Spanish Crown in the Netherlands in the 1550s and 1560s. As cited above, the privileges, customs, and institutions that largely served to shape the character of Hapsburg administration in the Low Countries were more precedential than explicit. The powers exercised by a given city, noble, or province were not infrequently subject to invalidation, enlargement, or repression depending on the nature of their relationship with either the reigning monarch or their appointed regent, and local potentates were often forced to compete for influence with royal officials imported from some other corner of the House of Hapsburg’s extensive domains. Even if the various privileges had at some point been made explicit, however, this somewhat ambiguous state of affairs would arguably have remained. The fact that the Hapsburg King of Spain was also the recognized feudal lord of the individual provinces of the Netherlands – he was the Count of Flanders, for example, and the Duke of Brabant, and the Count of Holland, and so forth – combined with the inability of either the States General or its various provincial counterparts to exercise much legislative authority, would still have made it something of an open question whether or not the provinces themselves had any standing upon which to offer protest to a claimed violation of their traditional rights. The authority and sovereignty of the individual states of the Hapsburg Netherlands were simply too nebulously-defined, or if defined, unrecognized, or if recognized, unenforced. An honest appraisal of the circumstances immediately preceding the outbreak of the Dutch Revolt in 1568 would therefore arguably have revealed that it wasn’t necessarily clear what the Spanish Crown or its representatives could or couldn’t do, what the cities, nobles, and states could or couldn’t expect, and with whom, in the end, paramount sovereignty ultimately resided.  

Bearing this is mind, the other parallels that Price attempted to draw between the abuses of the British Crown in America and of the Spanish Crown in the Netherlands become somewhat harder to reconcile. The North Ministry absolutely violated the charter of Massachusetts, for example, and arguably violated the charters of the other colonies as well. By comparison, it would be difficult to say that Spain violated the charters of the various provinces of the Netherlands because, as aforementioned, there weren’t really any charters in place to violate. By the same token, while successive British governments did levy taxes upon the American colonies in violation of their sovereign right to be taxed only by a government in which their enjoyed some measure of representation, the King of Spain – Philip II (1527-1598) – arguably possessed the right and authority to do exactly that in the provinces of the Netherlands as the sovereign ruler of the various counties and duchies therein. Furthermore, though the North Ministry did authorize the stationing of troops within the bounds of the Province of Massachusetts without the consent of either the inhabitants or government thereof, thereby violating the spirit – if not necessarily the letter – of one of the key guarantees of the Bill of Rights, Philip II’s earlier use of this same measure could not rightly be regarded in exactly the same light. Revolts having occurred in the Netherlands under both the Burgundians and the Hapsburgs since at least the mid-15th century, the presence of armed soldiers could hardly be said to have represented an innovation. Granted, popular resentment at the appearance of, say, a garrison of German soldiers dispatched from some possession or other of the Hapsburgs was certainly far from uncommon during that family’s period of rule over the Netherlands. But the fact remains that there were no formal legal prohibitions in place which would either have prevented the relevant authorities from taking such actions or offered censure in the event that they did.

This, in truth, forms the crux of the weakness embedded in the comparison Price attempted to offer. Rhetorically, his approach was sound enough. As with his evocation of the shame and frustration which surrounded the Corsican Crisis, his intention seemed to be to unfavorably compare Great Britain to one of its European rivals. In this case, rather than France, Price set his sights upon Spain, perennial bastion of Catholic supremacy, home of the Inquisition, and unrepentant practitioner of political absolutism. If, he ostensibly determined, he could convince his readers that Britain’s actions in America were as deplorable as Hapsburg Spain’s had been in the Netherlands, some people might actually be shocked into agitating for an end to the North Ministry’s military campaign. While the success of such an attempt would have required the average British reader of Observations to tacitly sympathize with the Dutch Republic and its inhabitants – a less than obvious impulse, given the fraught history between the British and Dutch peoples in the realms of commerce and naval superiority – it remained, on its face, a fairly reasonable approach. Price arguably spoiled it, however, by failing to recognize that Britain’s behavior in America was in many ways substantially worse than that of the Spanish Crown in the 16th and 17th century Netherlands.

Make no mistake, the attempts made by Philip II to excessively tax his Dutch subjects, to station foreign troops among them, and, crucially, to stamp out the burgeoning Protestant faith by persecuting non-Catholics and creating a Netherlands chapter of the Inquisition – a point notably absent from Price’s evaluation, it bears noting – were cruel, imperious, and morally unjustifiable. But neither Spain nor the extensive dominions of the Hapsburgs recognized anything like the guarantees written into the 17th century British Constitution which prohibited taxation without consent or the arbitrary use of standing armies. At the same time, the guarantees which the various provinces of the Netherlands believed they were entitled to took the form of unwritten customs rather than codified – and mutually agreed-upon – charters. Spain’s actions in the 16th century Netherlands, therefore, while by any measure undeniably deplorable, could not be said to have violated any unambiguous legal proscriptions, injunctions, or agreements. By comparison, the policies enacted by successive British governments and directed at the American colonies over the course of the 1760s and 1770s flagrantly infringed upon a number of explicitly enumerated constitutional protections embedded in both the Bill of Rights and in the various colonial charters to which the Crown was a party. That Price, as aforementioned, failed to recognize this fact, and thus failed to make use of the rhetorical power it embodied, would seem to represent something of an error on his part. His argument, in short, could have been stronger.

Friday, December 14, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part XVII: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain, contd.

            Next seeking evidence of the kind of behavior he believed his countrymen would have no trouble identifying as wholly dishonorable – and which, by comparison, might expose the dishonor in the actions of the North Ministry – Price turned his attention to a wide swath of European history ranging from the recent past to distant antiquity. The first of four examples he thus endeavored to present was one which could not but have still been fresh in the minds of his prospective audience, encompassing, as it did, events which took place less than a decade prior. “How have we felt for the brave Corsicans,” Price accordingly inquired, “In their struggle with the Genoese, and afterwards with the French government?” The occasion being referred to was the so-called “Corsican Crisis” of 1768-69, the outcome of which had caused the downfall of the government of the Duke of Grafton (1735-1811). Corsica, being a small island in the Mediterranean Sea located south of the coast of Liguria and north of the larger island of Sardinia, had been under the control of the Republic of Genoa for the better part of five centuries when, in the 1750s, a revolt broke out among its native inhabitants. The revolutionaries, led by one Pasquale Paoli (1725-1807), managed to successfully fight off Genoese authorities for nine years, at which point – despairing of success – the Genoese turned to the Kingdom of France for aid. France obliged, dispatched troops to the island in 1764, and erected a blockade of its major fortresses and ports. When this effort likewise resulted in failure – and with the Genoese now in debt to France for their assistance – a treaty was signed in 1768 whereby Corsica was effectively sold to the French in exchange for their forgiveness of Genoa’s obligations.
         
            The point at which this ostensibly regional power struggle became a matter of international importance – to the point of collapsing a British government by its outcome – lay chiefly in the relationship which the aforementioned Paoli sought to forge between his own provisional government and that of Great Britain. Under the leadership of Paoli, the self-proclaimed Corsican Republic adopted an exceedingly liberal constitution whereby all men aged twenty-five or above possessed the right to elect representatives every three years to a national legislature that met in the capital of Corte. News of this development – and of Paoli’s noted admiration for the British form of government – was well-received by authorities in Britain, many of whom both sympathized with the Corsican plight and perceived in the rebellion a means of thwarting the territorial ambitions of the Kingdom of France. In spite of these warm feelings towards the people of Corsica, however, the government of the Duke of Grafton declined to intervene upon France’s invasion of the island in 1768. While both Grafton and his foreign secretary, future Prime Minister Lord Shelburne (1737-1809), expressed alarm at the Corsican’s increasingly desperate state of affairs, they both likewise agreed that Britain was neither equipped nor inclined to interfere. Events then playing out in Britain’s American dependencies appeared to them of more pressing concern, and it was felt by them safer to appease the French than antagonize them unnecessarily.

            The result, for the Grafton ministry, was something of a paradox. Thanks to the efforts of people like James Boswell (1740-1795), a Scottish biographer who popularized sympathy for Corsica with the publication of a first-hand account of his 1765 journey to the island, British public opinion was very much on the side of military intervention. Donations were solicited and dispatched to the embattled islanders, a brace of cannons was ordered and sent from the famous Carron Ironworks in Falkirk, and public agitation steadily mounted for some form of rescue, either by Britain alone or in alliance with other states. Unfortunately for the Grafton Ministry, neither option appeared at that time to be particularly attractive. Having lost most of its traditional allies in the aftermath of the Seven Years War (1754-1763), Britain was in the midst of a period of diplomatic isolation at the time that the Corsican Crisis emerged. What little effort the aforementioned Shelburne expended to forge an anti-French coalition accordingly met with a lukewarm reception, and such efforts were ultimately and quickly suspended. As unilateral action at the same time appeared unwise due to the resources it would draw away from the increasingly restive American colonies, Grafton opted instead to do nothing at all. In due course, this proved a disastrous choice for Britain’s global reputation and the integrity of its government.

The French managed to inflict a final and crushing defeat upon the Corsicans at the Battle of Ponte Novu in May 1769, thus bringing an end to the Corsican Republic and driving many of its leaders – including Paoli himself – into exile abroad. In light of Britain’s accompanying inaction, authorities in France thereafter concluded that though the British still likely possessed the most powerful fleet in the world, their evident unwillingness to use it substantially reduced the threat it might have presented to French ambitions in Europe and elsewhere. Potential British allies were likewise dismayed by Grafton’s willingness to stand by in the face of French aggression, causing Britain’s political isolation to deepen even further. At home, meanwhile, the Grafton ministry was beset internally by ministerial disagreements and externally by a series of anonymous and highly critical letters under the penname “Junius” published in the London Public Advertiser beginning in January 1769. Seeing no way to recover from the associated setbacks – the loss of prestige among the nations of Europe, the loss of confidence among the British people – Grafton resigned in January, 1770 in favor of his Chancellor of the Exchequer, Lord North.

The conclusion which Richard Price attempted to draw from this series of events some eight years later in 1776 was essentially that the behavior of the Genoese and the French vis-à-vis their nominal Corsican subjects – a source of intense public displeasure in Britain at the time – was in fact no worse than the manner in which the North Ministry had thus far conducted itself in relation to the Thirteen Colonies. “Did GENOA [,]” he accordingly inquired, “Or FRANCE want more than an absolute command over their property and legislations; or the power of binding them in all cases whatsoever?” The answer to this question, though left unvoiced by Price, was an implicit “no,” thereby drawing a parallel between Britain’s claimed power to make such, “Laws and statutes [as] to bind the colonies and people of America [...] in all cases whatsoever” and France’s successful campaign to stamp out the liberal Corsican Republic and establish itself as the sole authority on the island. Truly, Price thus begged his readers consider, what was the difference? If, indeed, there were none, the implications became increasingly sinister.

The Corsicans, for example, had initially been subjects of the Republic of Genoa, and were then effectively traded to France in exchange for the forgiveness of a debt. “All such cessions of one people to another,” Price declared, “Are disgraceful to human nature. But if our claims are just, may not we also, if we please, CEDE the Colonies to France?” Again, the purpose of this kind of comparison was to cast doubt on the relevant policy of the sitting British government. If, as Price affirmed, the North Ministry regarded the colonies in essentially the same manner as the Genoese and the French had regarded Corsica, then it stood to reason that Lord North could, if he so desired, sell, cede, or donate Virginia, Massachusetts, or indeed any one of their number to any foreign power for any reason. Such an action would, after all, have fallen well within the bounds of “binding” the colonies “in all cases whatsoever,” and woe betide any authority in America who would dare to argue against it. The only guarantee with which the luckless colonists might take comfort – indeed, the principle difference Price was willing to admit between the Franco-Corsican relationship and that which existed between Britain and America – was the fact that, “The Corsicans were not descended from the people who governed them, but that the Americans are.” Sentiment, then, was the only check on the British government’s use of a power which it tacitly claimed to hold. Having lately witnessed the extent of British sentiment – at Lexington and Concord and at Bunker Hill – the inhabitants of America thus protected from being treated like chattel could surely have been forgiven for finding this cold comfort indeed.

Price’s aim, of course, was as much to shame his countrymen into righteous action as offer sympathy to the suffering inhabitants of the Thirteen Colonies. Citing the Corsican Crisis arguably helped to accomplish the former by both recalling the feelings of anger and frustration its outcome had inspired as well as casting the government of Lord North in the same role in 1776 as the aggressive and imperious French had played in 1769. A less flattering comparison would indeed have been difficult to conceive of, France being Britain’s inveterate rival for continental – and, increasingly, global – hegemony and as well as its spiritual and moral opposite. Whereas the British held fast to the Anglican faith – a religion, they claimed, befitting a free people – the French were dedicated Catholics whose practices appeared to mainstream British perception to be invariably steeped in superstition, secrecy, and an excessive submission to authority. Likewise, while the British people beheld their system of government – over which every county and borough could claim its share of influence – with surpassing pride, their counterparts in France were comparatively uninvolved in their country’s administration, power having long been concentrated in the hands of the monarch, his ministers, the aristocracy, and the church. Granting that reality was, as ever, more complicated than these generalization otherwise indicate – Britain having had its share of Catholic, France its share of Protestants, and neither government being as virtuous or as tyrannical as most British observers would have claimed – contemporary British sentiment towards France nonetheless largely pivoted on exactly these kinds of oversimplifications and half-formed prejudices. For Price to equate Great Britain with France, therefore, in the context of the contemporary Anglo-American relationship, would have been more or less the equivalent of accusing an exceptionally pious Christian of giving aid and comfort to Satan himself. Provided that the claim was not dismissed out of hand, one might fairly expect a great deal of soul-searching to follow as the accused endeavored to account for their transgressions and make sincere and immediate amends.

Friday, December 7, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part XVI: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain, contd.

            The justice – or rather injustice – of the burgeoning conflict between Great Britain and the Thirteen Colonies having been well and fully established over the course of Part II, Section III of his Observations, Richard Price next proceeded to discuss in Section IV the extent to which he believed that the honor of the British state and people were particularly entangled with the outcome of said struggle. The resulting examination, presented under the title “Of the Honour of the Nation, as affected by the War with America [,]” though adopting a rather broad view of the subject at hand, nevertheless managed to frame the position and actions of the contemporary British government with a remarkable degree of moral clarity and rhetorical force. History was Price’s medium of choice, both recent and ancient, and his aim was to translate the shame and odium his countrymen might have been given to feel about a specific incident from the past into a clearer understanding of what their own government was attempting in the present. In so doing, the author of Observations effectively demonstrated the consistency of some of his most loudly-voiced convictions, his continued ambivalence – if not outright disdain – towards the moral character of classical antiquity, and his urgent belief that the events then transpiring in distant America embodied ill portents for the people of Britain proper.
             
            As with previous sections of Observations, Section IV began with Price’s citation of the particular claim he intended to refute. Specifically, it was that which purported, on behalf of the sitting government, “That our honor is engaged; and that we cannot recede without the most humiliating concessions.” Price’s first point in opposition to this stance was a relatively simple one, though by his own admission he rather regretted the fact of it. “A distinction should be made [,]” he avowed,

Between the nation and its rulers. It is melancholy that there should be ever any reason for making such a distinction. A government is, or ought to be, nothing but an institution for collecting and carrying into execution the will of the people. But so far is this from being in general the fact, that the measures of government, and the sense of the people, are sometimes in direct opposition to one another; nor does it often happen that any certain conclusion  can be drawn from the one to the other.
         
Perhaps the most striking element of this passage is the evident gulf it described between the optimism with which Price envisioned government and the sense of mistrust with which he observed it. Granted, previous sections of his Observations attested quite powerfully to his believe that the institutions of the contemporary British state no longer served to accurately represent the interests of the general population. He had also already made it substantially clear that he perceived the British ministerial elite as being almost wholly in thrall to a coterie of bankers, financiers, and merchants whose overriding commercial interests where largely at odds with those of the British people as a whole.

To some extent, however, these specific criticisms constituted  mere sideswipes at a much larger issue. Describing Parliament as unrepresentative and government as corrupt was, after all, something less than stating plainly and simply that the British state and the British people had become separate to the point of working at cross purposes. Corruption and a lack of representation in government were most definitely serious causes of dysfunction to which Price was justifiably motivated to seek some form of remedy. But a state of affairs in which the people wanted fundamentally different – even opposing – things than their government could fairly be characterized as a full-blown disorder. Price’s admission that, “The measures of government, and the sense of the people, are sometimes in direct opposition to one another” could therefore be said to constitute his gravest evaluation yet of the health and wellbeing of contemporary British civilization. After all, a government that works directly against the wishes of its constituents essentially constitutes a rejection of the very definition of government itself. It is not merely dysfunctional, but broken. It does not simply function badly, but rather ceases to function at all.

Interestingly enough, though Price was speaking from within the context of late 1770s Britain – a time and place freighted with any number of very specific issues and influences – exactly this kind of sentiment became a staple of mainstream American political discourse beginning in the middle 1790s. Driven to increasingly virulent factionalism by the pressures exerted on the nation’s yet nascent political culture during the tumultuous post-war years and the debates which accompanied the ratification of the United States Constitution, Americans entered the last decade of the 18th century arguably more disunited politically than they had been since the first stirrings of the Revolution in the middle 1760s. And while formal political parties were slow to form – consequent to widespread opposition to the concept – the ideological cleavages which would come to define the next several decades of American political life were very much in evidence. Generally speaking, these divisions resolved themselves around two basic philosophical poles, being advocacy for a powerful central government and support for powerful state governments, respectively. The former, falling under the label of Federalism, argued for the creation of national means to address national priorities – from debt, to infrastructure, to the military, to trade – and tended to find its strongest supporter among merchants, financiers, manufacturers, and soldiers. The latter position, adopting the equally vague title of Republicanism, meanwhile conversely advocated for political decentralization as a means of preserving civil liberties, championed policies like easy access to credit and free trade, and was most popular among Southern plantation owners, yeoman farmers, and urban tradesmen.

It ought to come as no surprise that it was the Republican faction – or Republican Party, or Democratic-Republicans – whose leaders and scribes very soon found cause to echo many of the sentiments expressed by the likes of Richard Price in their attempts to describe the dangers they perceived in the governments of President George Washington (1732-1799) and President John Adams (1735-1826). The Federalists who then held the reins of power – led though most of this period by Alexander Hamilton (1755-1804) – were variously accused by opposition Republicans of being pseudo-monarchists, slavish Anglophiles, tyrants-in-waiting, and corrupt aristocrats whose financial interests and lust for power had long since overpowered whatever conviction they might once had held to preserve the liberties of their fellow Americans. Republican faction leader Thomas Jefferson (1743-1826) captured the extent to which he believed this served to separate the Federalists in power from their nominal constituents in a 1798 letter to fellow Virginian John Taylor (1753-1824), stating that,  

The body of our countrymen is substantially republican through every part of the Union. It was the irresistible influence & popularity of Gen Washington, played off by the cunning of Hamilton, which turned the government over to anti-republican hands, or turned the republican members, chosen by the people, into anti-republicans.

Note the dichotomy that this description presents. The people, Jefferson affirmed, were naturally republican, while the government, by way of influence and cunning, was anti-republican. The difference being inherently artificial and contrived, the natural state of government in America – and thus the natural connection between the people and their administrators – had thus by definition been disrupted.

            A more specific – and arguably more significant – example of this same characterization can be found in the public criticisms Jefferson offered to certain Adams Administration policies in the so-called Kentucky Resolutions. Alarmed by the passage and implementation of the Alien and Sedition Acts (1798), Jefferson – then serving as Vice-President under Adams – anonymously penned a series of condemnations that were subsequently ratified and published by the Kentucky state legislature. The general thrust of these remonstrances was that the relevant statutes appeared to place the national government above the authority of either the Constitution or the American people. Under their terms, Jefferson explained,

The general government may place any act they think proper on the list of crimes, and punish it themselves, whether enumerated or not enumerated by the Constitution as cognizable by them […] they may transfer its cognizance to the President […] who may himself be the accuser, counsel, judge, and jury, whose suspicions may be the evidence, his order the sentence, his officer the executioner, and his breast the sole record of the transaction […] And the barriers of the Constitution thus swept from us all, no rampart now remains against the passions and the power of a majority of Congress, to protect from a like exportation, or other grievous punishment, the minority of the same body, the legislatures, judges, governors, and counsellors of the states, nor their other peaceable inhabitants, who may venture to reclaim the constitutional rights and liberties of the states and people [.]

Of particular note in this passage is Jefferson’s identification of the President and Congress alike as shared source of distress, as well as his evident belief in the efficacy of the Constitution. It was not the very notion of a national government that the leader of the Republican faction feared, it seemed – though his other writings would show that he certainly harbored concerns – but rather the way that said government was used.

The “barriers of the Constitution” and its various enumerated powers were unfortunately only as dependable as the parties involved desired them to be. That the Federalists in Congress and in the cabinet of President Adams had, by Jefferson’s reckoning, chosen to ignore these essential protections in service of their own partisan pursuits thus formed the core of his criticism. Like the North Ministry – whom many of its members had ironically risked their lives to oppose in the 1770s and 1780s – the contemporary Federalist establishment embodied to Jefferson and his Republican cohorts a thing apart from the people whose interests they claimed to represent. The general population, he affirmed in his aforementioned letter to John Taylor, were “substantially republican” while the government was somehow in the hands of “anti-republicans.” The people had chosen to ratify a Constitution blessed with numerous checks upon the abuse of legislative or executive power – ranging from prohibitions against concentrations of authority to protections of due process – while the Adams Administration had seemingly made it possible for the President to act in certain matters of criminal justice as, “The accuser, counsel, judge, and jury,” and left vulnerable, “The minority of [Congress], the legislatures, judges, governors, and counsellors of the states, [and] their other peaceable inhabitants [.]”

One could arguably come no closer than this to the criticism Richard Price had leveled at his own government two decades earlier. For that matter, the further similarities between Price’s condemnations of contemporary British society and the standard Republican appraisal of the culture of government and business fostered by their Federalist opponents – i.e. a denunciation of excessive wealth and corruption, advocacy for political de-centralization, etc. – would seem to affirm the existence of a strong ideological connection between the pre-Revolutionary Old Whig reformism of dissident British intellectuals and statesmen like Richard Price and the post-Revolutionary agrarian populism of opposition figures like Thomas Jefferson. And though the question of whether this connection was direct or indirect – conscious or unconscious – is almost certainly too involved to delve into here, the possibility nevertheless bears acknowledging that some of the core tenets of Jeffersonian Republicanism may have been as much a product of and development from earlier trends in British political culture and public discourse as Hamiltonian Federalism, American Constitutionalism, or the very impulse to resistance that sparked the American Revolution. 
         
            All that being having said, the subject at hand once more demands attention. Price, though evidently keen to point out very early in Part II, Section IV of his Observations that the British government and the British people were not necessarily of like minds in all things – and that he furthermore wasn’t certain whether a dishonor suffered by said government would necessarily reflect at all upon the integrity of its constituents – nevertheless seemed quite willing to put this same assertion aside when examining the fundamental moral implications of the North Ministry’s campaign to quell the ongoing rebellion in British America. Whether the British people generally agreed with Lord North or not was evidently of little consequence in this particular context. In either case, Price avowed, “The disgrace to which a kingdom must submit by making concessions, is nothing to that of being the aggressors in an unrighteous quarrel; and dignity, in such circumstances, consists in retracting freely, speedily, and magnanimously.” This declaration, like so many of Price’s condemnations of the North Ministry’s conduct, served to deconstruct the orthodox British government position by essentially turning it on its head.

To the argument that the nation’s honor had become so wholly tied to the successful pacification of America that no retreat was thought possible without suffering disgrace, Price accordingly countered that there could be no honor in the victory then being pursued. The British cause was fundamentally unjust, the war a wholly unnecessary conflict between members of the same imperial family, and honor could only be salvaged – not won, but salvaged – if wrong was admitted and magnanimity freely offered. Seeking perhaps to place a final emphasis on the validity of this position, Price then proceeded to offer a quote from William Pitt (1708-1778), Whig statesman, staunch opponent of institutional corruption, and noted friend of the American colonies. “RECTITUDE IS DIGNITY [,]” Price cited the former Prime Minister as having said, “OPPRESSION ONLY IS MEANNESS; AND JUSTICE, HONOR.” Having failed to abide by this maxim, the North Ministry and its supporters could make no claim to the possession of honor in their pursuit of victory in colonial America.

Friday, November 30, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part XV: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain, contd.

In the third of five sections Richard Price devoted in Part II of his Observations to examining the conduct of the burgeoning conflict between Great Britain and the Thirteen Colonies – with the aim, as aforesaid, of calling said conduct into question – he proceeded to turn his attention to what he described as, “The Policy of the War with America.” His specific aim therein was essentially to establish that the stated objective of the sitting government of Lord North – i.e. to restore the previously existing relationship between Britain and its American dependencies – was exceedingly unlikely to occur in consequence of the tactics being deployed by that selfsame administration.

The analysis Price deployed to this end encompassed an admirably wide scope of contemporary foreign and domestic policy – from trade, to taxation, to banking – though the cogency of his reasoning was not always as consistent as he might have hoped. On the subject of the mercantile intercourse which had previously existed between Great Britain and its American dependencies, for example, the author of Observations keenly and effectively noted that claims made by the North Ministry to want nothing more than the resumption of harmonious trade were almost wholly at odds with the effects of the various measures that same government had endeavored to enact in the 1760s and 1770s. Similarly astute was Price’s observation that, prior to the onset of the Anglo-American crisis, Britain already enjoyed a tremendous degree of influence over almost every aspect of life and government in colonial America, and that subsequent attempts to extend this influence could not but represent a species of uncommon greed on the part of the ministry of Lord North. His accounting of Britain’s precarious monetary position was markedly less shrewd, however. Capable though Price no doubt was of comprehending and articulating the complexities of 18th century lending practices, interest rates, and currency values, his personal, ideological, and moral disdain for the luxury and corruption he believed was inevitably generated by easy access to large sums of money appeared to weigh to a greater extent upon his conclusions in this matter than did a rigorous accounting of the facts at hand. Bearing this in mind, one is rightly bound to consider to what degree the whole of Price’s defense of the ongoing America resistance to the North Ministry and its policies was spurred by a kind of spontaneous sympathy on his part to the injustices the colonists had been forced to endure, and to what extent the man was already inclined to question the virtue of any authority whose stated aim was something other than wholesale reform of Britain’s public institutions and political culture.

But let us return, for the moment, to the purpose of the North Ministry’s campaign in America. It would seem to warrant examination the degree to which Price first endeavored to make it clear at the outset of Part II, Section III that said government’s stated goal of reestablishing the accustomed supremacy of Great Britain over the colonies was an acceptable rationale only if it could be demonstrated that some form of advantage was to be thereby derived. Specifically, he explained that,

The desire of maintaining authority is warrantable, only so far as it is the means of promoting some end, and doing some good; and that, before we resolve to spread famine and fire through a country in order to make it acknowledge our authority, we ought to be assured that great advantages will arise not only to ourselves but to the country we wish to conquer.

A fairly durable rationale being thus established – that one country could justifiably assert its control over another only if it could be demonstrated that both parties stood to derive an advantage from the resulting connection – it thereby stood to reason that an inability to meet the appropriate criteria would render the relevant association – or actions taken to support it – wholly indefensible. The reason for this, Price explained, once more echoing John Locke, was that any species of authority, in order to be considered legitimate in the eyes of those who experience its power, must serve some kind of purpose outside of its own perpetuation. Governments that accordingly fail to, “Preserve the peace and to secure the safety of the state [,]” can thereby be considered, by their very nature, “Tyrannical, as far as [they constitute] a needless and wanton exercise of power [.]”

Every authority in every nation on earth was bound to measure itself by this basic standard of purpose, Britain no more or no less than any other. That Britain was the particular focus of Price’s concern and suspicion therefore owed itself – alongside that fact that Price was of course a resident of the same and a noted and longstanding critic of its institutions – to certain specific events that had recently occurred within the context of the Anglo-American crisis. First, in light of his stated conviction that, “A love of power for its own sake [is] inherent in human nature [,]” Price questioned the degree to which the British reaction against the resistance offered by the Thirteen Colonies was motivated by a regard for the law and a desire to restore some semblance of peace and security. On the contrary, he offered, “Is it not the opposition they make to our pride and not any injury they have done to us, that is the secret spring of our present animosity against them?” Had not the British people grown accustomed to looking upon the inhabitants of America as a nation, “Whom we have a right to order as we please, who hold their property at our disposal, and who have no other law than our will [?]” Price certainly believed it possible that this was the case, and wondered if certain of his countrymen might not agree if they examined their feelings on the matter more closely. “Perhaps,” he thus entreated,

They would become sensible, that it was a spirit of domination, more than a regard to the true interests of this country, that lately led so many of them, which such savage folly, to address the throne for the slaughter of their brethren in America, if they will not submit to them; and to make offers of their lives and fortunes for that purpose.

While it wouldn’t be fair to say that Price was wrong to thus question the motivations of the ministers and supporters of the government of Lord North, it nonetheless bears consideration the degree to which he could possibly have known for certain whether or not the relevant individuals were indeed acting wholly out of a sense of wounded vanity. 

The statements issued by the Crown – under the auspices of the North Ministry – in the weeks and months following the commencement of hostilities in April, 1775, while not necessarily all that kind to the leaders of the American resistance, could hardly be described as calling “for the slaughter of their brethren in America [.]” The Proclamation of Rebellion, for example, issued principally in response to the British defeat at the Battle of Bunker Hill (June 17th, 1775), went little further than referring to the instigators of the incipient colonial rebellion as, “Dangerous and ill designing men,” who had forgotten, “The allegiance which they owe to the power that has protected and supported them [.]” They were “traitorous,” to be sure, as were their “conspiracies” and their “correspondence,” and their actions most definitely constituted rebellion. But neither the king nor his government seemed yet intent on condemning anyone to slaughter. The Speech from the Throne offered in October of that same year was similarly restrained in its use of invective. The instigators of the relevant disturbance in the colonies were guilty of, “Gross misrepresentations,” it affirmed, had deployed a, “Torrent of violence” to ensure the cooperation of their fellow subjects in America, and were now engaged in a, “rebellious war […] manifestly carried on for the purpose of establishing an independent empire.” Doubtless the body of delegates then seated in the Continental Congress would have loudly and explicitly asserted that these were all of them false claims, and that describing the actions being undertaken in defense of American liberties as, “Revolt, hostility and rebellion [,]” represented nothing short of slander. But promises of a massacre, they most certainly were not.

By couching their official reaction in the language of contemporary diplomacy, law, and war, George III and his ministers had thus effectively made it that much harder to determine whether they were acting out of a sense of duty or betrayal, pragmatism or pride. To his credit – and in spite of his evident affirmation to the contrary – Price seemed to be aware of this fact, and endeavored to approach his examination of Britain’s conduct vis-à-vis the American colonies with an appropriate focus on action as well as motivation. If the policies advanced by the North Ministry – or by its recent predecessors – indeed appeared conducive to the salvation and strengthening of the Anglo-American relationship, then there would accordingly seem to be no reason at all to call the intentions of the relevant government into question. Having attempted in good faith to mend an increasingly frayed connection, whatever errors they had committed as a result could consequently have been excused and forgiven as the honest mistakes of an ultimately well-meaning administration. If, however, it might plainly be demonstrated that the actions variously pursued by successive British governments could never have resulted in the restoration and/or reinforcement of the Anglo-American relationship – or even seemed destined to do injury to the best interests of the parties involved – it would appear far from unreasonable to conclude that the purpose of said governments were something less than virtuous and pure. Having determined to wound America at the cost of wounding themselves in turn, the authorities responsible could not but be characterized as having adopted a vicious and contradictory response to having doubt cast upon the extent of their power.

Proceeding to apply this investigative framework to specific aspects of the North Ministry’s administration in America, Price first hit upon the ostensibly reckless manner in which said government had endeavored to pursue certain policies wholly and demonstrably inimical to the preservation of the already much-strained relationship between Great Britain and its American dependencies. To that end, he first set himself to enumerating the many and various pieces of legislation that had been laid by successive British governments upon either the trade of the American colonies or the revenues thereof. The Molasses Act (1733), he affirmed, was the first of these, passed in the sixth year of the reign of George II (1683-1760) with the intention – by taxing competing products – of increasing the sale in America of sugar, molasses, and the spirits derived from either that had been produced in the British West Indies. “As the act had the appearance of being only a regulation of trade,” Price was keen to note, “The colonies submitted to it [.]” Likewise did they submit to an amended version of the same legislation in 1765 – the so-called Sugar Act – though it was pursued with the express intention of, “Raising a revenue in America.” This fact, Price avowed, was cause for some alarm, “And produced discontents and remonstrances, which might have convinced our rulers that this was tender ground, on which it became them to tread very gently.” Nothing like a sustained uproar was then observed, however, for it seemed that the inhabitants of British America thought it yet still permissible for Parliament to claim the right to tax them externally. Peace was thus preserved, for the time being, though the limits of American indulgence had been nearly approached.

These limits were subsequently breached with the passage of the Stamp Act (1765). “This being,” Price affirmed,

An attempt to tax [the colonists] INTERNALLY; and a direct attack on their property, by a power which would not suffer itself to be questioned; which eased itself by loading them and to which it as impossible to fix any bounds; they were thrown at once, from one end of the continent to the other, into resistance and rage.

Vehement though the resulting public reaction most certainly was, however – ranging from hostile newspaper editorials, public demonstrations, and organized boycotts to riots that resulted in the harassment of tax officials and the destruction of public and private property – even these fervent expressions of popular discontent represented only a temporary breach of the colonists seemingly concerted intention to exercise the greatest degree possible of moderation and forbearance. Once the government of the Marquess of Rockingham (1730-1782) secured the repeal of the Stamp Act in March, 1766, the colonists showed themselves perfectly willing to ignore the implications of the accompanying Declaratory Act – the text of which stated that Parliament would continue to possess, “Full power and authority to make laws and statutes […] to bind the colonies and people of America [...] in all cases whatsoever” – and return to a state of peaceful intercourse with their fellow subjects in Britain. The colonists were perhaps not particularly encouraged by this parting shot on the part of Rockingham – this stubborn claim to hold a power which the inhabitants of British America had never consented to bestow – but as Price asserted, “They would undoubtedly have suffered us (as the people of Ireland have done) to enjoy our declaratory law.” Thus, yet again, peace was preserved.

            This was not to be the case indefinitely, of course. For whatever reason, in accordance with whatever impulse, successive British governments in the 1760s and 1770s evidently made it a common objective to continually test the limits of the Anglo-American relationship. Case in point, Price explained, “Little more than a year after the repeal of the Stamp-Act, when all was peace, a third act was passed, imposing duties payable in America on tea, paper, glass, painters colours, &c.” As one might well have expected, the result of this attempt to once more tax the colonies for the purpose of generating revenue – in the form of the so-called Townshend Duties (passed between June, 1767 and July, 1768) – was the resumption of civil demonstrations, editorial condemnation, and organized boycotts. Customs officials were once more harassed, an ultimately failed attempt was made by Massachusetts Governor Francis Bernard (1712-1779) to have certain of the instigators sent to Britain to stand trial for treason, and four British regiments were dispatched to Boston in order aid in reasserting the authority of the Crown’s various agents. Once more made conscious of the fact that efforts to tax the colonies would never be wholly frictionless, the British government – now led by the aforementioned Lord North – engineered the repeal of all but one of the odious duties, the exception being that placed on tea. While this last measure was retained, Price avowed, “In order to maintain a shew of dignity” – hardly a cause to which the beleaguered colonies would have been likely to lend their assistance – the effort nonetheless, “Answered its intended purposes.” The colonists were forced only to avoid purchasing one imported commodity instead of several, Anglo-American trade was permitted once more to recover, and customs agents were no longer to fear being chased out of their homes in the middle of the night by torch-bearing mobs. Price affirmed that this state of affairs would have remained undisturbed, “And even tea would perhaps in time have been gradually admitted, had not the evil genius of Britain stepped forth once more to embroil the Empire.”

            Granting that Price’s choice of words – i.e. “evil genius” – represented something of an overstatement, he was not necessarily wrong to suggest that the North Ministry’s actions following the repeal of the Townshend Duties were difficult to fathom if they could not be attributed to malicious intent. The desire of that government to prop up the flagging fortunes of the East India Company was understandable enough, at least. Having suffered for the loss of the American market for its tea, it was determined that the best method for encouraging a reversal of this state of affairs was for Company product to be sold in the colonies free of all taxes save for a pittance of three pence on every pound purchased. Being thus presented with the choice of going without tea altogether, purchasing illegally smuggled tea – the transportation and sale of which was the subject of continued condemnation and punishment – or purchasing the now cheap and plentiful Company tea, it was hoped that the colonists would take what was obviously the simplest path forward and begin buying what was on offer. In so doing, it was hoped that the withering fortunes of an essential institution of the British Empire might be bolstered at the same time that the inhabitants of America could be made to break their self-imposed boycott and tacitly acknowledge the right of Parliament to lay taxes on their internal commerce. While Price affirmed that this, “Snare was too gross to escape the notice of the Colonies [,]” the residents thereof nevertheless went little farther than refusing to unload the product in their ports. The exception to this otherwise peaceful refusal to cooperate in a scheme intended to trick them into surrendering an essential liberty occurred in Boston, Price allowed, wherein, “Some persons in disguise buried [the offending goods] in the sea.” And though he offered no judgment in the text of his Observations as to the righteousness or folly of this action – that being the much-mythologized Boston Tea Party of December 16th, 1773 – he did allow that the people of Massachusetts, in his opinion, would likely have been willing to make adequate compensation for the British property thereby destroyed provided that such compensation represented the whole of the punishment they were required to suffer.

            That this was not to be the case should very likely go without saying. For, in addition to the Boston Port Act – to which, Price once more asserted, “The province might possibly have submitted, and a sufficient saving would have been gained for the honor of the nation” – the North Ministry secured the passage of the aforementioned Massachusetts Government Act, the Administration of Justice Act, and the Quebec Act, all by the end of June, 1774. Combined with the four British regiments stationed in Boston following the tumults occasioned by the Townshend Duties, the people of Massachusetts were effectively left under military occupation, with no government other than that which Parliament granted them, devoid of trade with the outside world, incapable of trying certain offenders in their own courts of law, and robbed of the ability to migrate westward as their needs and their desires inclined them. All else that had been laid upon the colonies – as early as 1733 and as late as 1773 – while perhaps not likely to have enamored the inhabitants thereof to the British governments responsible, had not proven themselves beyond the ability of the American temper to endure. They had accepted the taxation of their external trade as being for the benefit of the empire at large. They had consented to a Parliamentary claim of an absolute right to tax their internal commerce so long as it was not unduly exercised. They had even managed to make their peace with the existence of a standing army in their midst over whom they could exercise not the slightest control. Now and then, in response to a policy they felt was unjust, they had certainly been willing to make their displeasure known, sometimes to the point of physical violence. But always, once the policy in question had been rescinded, they returned to their accustomed state of peaceful forbearance. Clearly, in spite of everything they had been made to suffer, these were a people willing to go to significant lengths to preserve the status quo.
                            
            Such a saintly expression of patience was not without its limits, however. Tolerant though the colonists plainly were, they had at every occasion maintained that they were under no circumstances willing to surrender the liberties to which they felt they were entitled by birth. They might have suffered to see them bent to some degree, in the name of preserving harmonious relations between themselves and their fellow subjects in Britain. But such gestures of accommodation were under no circumstances meant to give permission for further encroachments upon their basic civil rights. The popular clamor aroused by the passage of the Stamp Act in 1765 and the Townshend Duties in 1767-68 should have served as ample evidence of this essential truth. The inhabitants of British American were willing to suffer the taxation of their external trade, limited taxation of their internal trade – so long as it was relatively easy to avoid making payment – and even the deployment of armed soldiers to their streets. But they never bore any of it quietly, and, in such instances as came particularly close to forcing them to acknowledge their supposed subservience to the British government, made the nature and intensity of their discontent impossible to ignore. Such was Price’s analysis, at least. Looking back upon the aforementioned mixture of patience and conviction with which the colonists comported themselves during the 1760s and 1770s, and in light of the events of the Boston Tea Party, he affirmed in text of his Observations that,

All who knew any thing of the temper of the Colonies saw that the effect of all sudden accumulation of vengeance, would probably be not intimidating but exasperating them, and driving them into a general revolt.

The North Ministry, unfortunately, appeared truly not to know anything of the temper of the colonies. All evidence to the contrary, “They believed that the malcontents in the Colony of Massachusetts were a small party, headed by a few fractious men […] and that, the issue would prove, in a few months, order, tranquility, and submission.” Events would very quickly show otherwise.

            At this stage in his retelling of the events of 1765-1775, Price once again saw fit to call explicitly into question the sincerity of the government of Lord North in its dealings with the Thirteen Colonies. The members and supporters of that government, he affirmed, did not believe that opposition to its policies was a conviction widely held in America, or that the colonies otherwise unaffected by the events transpiring in Massachusetts would seek to make common cause with the same. Difficult as it might have been to credit an otherwise talented group of statesmen with being so exceedingly shortsighted, the fact of it was at the very least possible. That being said, once the colonies had offered their collective reaction to the passage of the aforementioned punitive acts – in the form of the Continental Congress and its America-wide non-importation agreement – these same ministers would have had no reason to any longer doubt the conviction of the offended colonists or the degree to which they were willing to actively affirm their rights. But while an honest desire to reassert the customary relationship between the colonies and the British government would seem to have required at this stage a basic reassessment of certain policies and a rededication to finding some form of accommodation, the North Ministry instead plunged stubbornly ahead.

             Having been surprised and even frightened, as Price described it, by the vehemence of the colonial reaction to the passage of the aforementioned punitive legislation, Lord North and his cabinet nevertheless refused to abandon their goal of securing the submission of British America to the absolute authority of Parliament. To that end, he affirmed,

A proposal was sent to the Colonies, called Conciliatory; and the substance of which was, that if any of them would raise such sums as should be demanded of them by taxing themselves, the Parliament would forbear to tax them.

Conciliatory though this offer was evidently intended to be, even a moment’s reflection reveals it to be anything but. The substance of it, Price declared, was something to the effect of, “If you will tax yourselves BY OUR ORDER, we will save ourselves the trouble of taxing you.” The best that such a scheme could possibly have done is save face on the part of the affected colonies by giving to them some degree of discretion as to how and from where the relevant revenue was raised. It would not have addressed the question of whether Parliament was legally entitled to make such a demand of the colonial legislatures – answered, by the colonies, emphatically in the negative – and thus could never have served to settle the disagreement at hand. The colonies, now collectively represented in the Continental Congress, accordingly rejected the proposal, and set themselves to the task of establishing the aforementioned boycott on British goods and fortifying their respective defenses in the event that armed resistance became necessary.

            Though it may seem scarcely possible to believe, Price asserted that at this point in the evolution of the Anglo-American crisis the government of Lord North made what would appear to be yet another very serious mistake. In spite of their numbers, the resources at their disposal, and their clear and demonstrated ability to engage in highly successful efforts of collective organization, the members of the North Ministry continued at this crucial moment to think of the people of Massachusetts,

As nothing but a mob, who would be soon routed and forced into obedience. It was even believed, that a few thousands of our army might march through all America, and make all quiet wherever they went. Under this conviction our ministers did not dread urging the Province of Massachusetts-Bay into rebellion, by ordering their army to seize their stores, and to take up some of their leading men.

As with every other measure that had been taken by successive British governments since 1765, aimed at securing the complete submission of the American colonies to the authority of Parliament, this attempt also resulted in failure. The people, Price avowed, took up the arms which long practice and recent preparation had readied them to use, British attempts to seize American munitions were repelled, and a British attack on a colonial position outside occupied Boston, while successful, was accomplished at an alarming cost of blood and talent. “Some of our best Generals,” Price accordingly lamented, “And the bravest of our troops, are now disgracefully and miserably imprisoned in Boston.—A horrid civil war is commenced:—And the empire is distracted and convulsed.” There would seem to have been, by Price’s reckoning, only one explanation as to how this turn of events could possibly have come to pass.

It could not have been commerce, for the colonies had long-since shown themselves perfectly willing to render up any number of commercial advantages upon request by Parliament and the Crown. “They gave up the power of making sumptuary laws,” Price thus affirmed, “And exposed themselves to all the evils of an increasing and wasteful luxury, because we were benefited by vending among them the materials of it.” In light of the degree to which the original Puritan founders of the Massachusetts Bay Colony and the Plymouth Colony strove to create societies purged of sin by enacting legal restrictions upon what a person could wear, what kinds of games they could play, and whether they could smoke tobacco or drink alcohol, this would indeed seem to represent a significance concession on their part to the mercantile interests of Great Britain and its traders. Just so, Price continued, “The iron with which providence had blessed their country, they were required by laws, in which they acquiesced, to transport hither, that our people might be maintained by working it for them into nails, ploughs, axes, &c.” As it happened, the terms of the Iron Act (1750) had indeed placed fairly unequivocal restrictions on the ability of interested colonial entrepreneurs to erect any more iron works than already existed, thus conveying a definite advantage upon such British manufacturers as were now able to purchase duty-free pig-iron from the colonies, use the resulting savings to expand their operations, and flood the America market with cheap wrought iron and refined steel.

            Granted, there was more to both of these scenarios that Price seemed willing to admit. While it was certainly to the benefit of British industry – particularly in the realms of luxury textiles, distilling, and artisan metalwork – for the New England Puritan to abandon their various socio-legal prohibitions against personal indulgence, the relevant movement away from strict sumptuary proscriptions did not come solely at the behest of contemporary British governments. Eager though British merchants most definitely were to obtain greater access to American consumers, and strict though the Puritan-dominated governments in New England generally remained in their respective interpretations of what was permissible and what was forbidden, the truth of the matter is that within a few decades of the start of the colonial project, enough residents of the relevant colonies had taken to defying the sumptuary laws that they ceased to be actively enforced. It may be said, therefore, that while British traders naturally wasted no time in seizing upon the opportunity to sell their wares in this previously much-restricted market – thus accomplishing the further integration of New England into the larger imperial economy – neither they nor their sponsors in government created the opportunity itself. By the same token, while the Iron Act did seek to create a set of circumstances by which it was almost certainly cheaper to purchase finished iron and steel products from British manufacturers than from the few American refineries that were permitted to exist, the fact of the legislation itself tells only half the tale. As with the earlier Molasses Act (1733) and the subsequent duties upon tea, colonial Americans were perfectly willing and able to accept the passage of a restrictive commercial law like the Iron Act in public while taking such measures as were necessary to evade its terms in private. As Parliament yet still lacked sufficient means to police the enforcement of most any of its colonial policies, iron refineries and forges remained quite common in contemporary British America, particularly in such cases as their owners and operators were members of the socio-political elite in colonies like Maryland and Virginia.

            Despite his somewhat one-sided representation of the character of the Anglo-American relationship – i.e. the colonies bending over backwards to be accommodating to the vast majority of Britain’s desires and priorities – Price was nevertheless correct to assert that, prior to the middle 1760s, the American colonies had shown themselves quite willing to accept their place as an appendage of the larger British Empire. Privately, certain residents thereof might have questioned the wisdom or the necessity of certain policies or statutes, even to the point of taking steps to actively evade them. But they evidently did not feel inclined to call into question the legality of such measures as the Molasses Act or the Iron Act. Parliament, they evidently concluded, was within its rights to attempt to regulate the economy of the British Empire as a whole, and to take such action to that end, vis-à-vis the American colonies, as appeared to be necessary. That the colonists themselves freely purchased British products – from the metalwork prejudiced by the terms of the Iron Act to the luxury goods at one time prohibited by law in the Puritan jurisdictions of Massachusetts and Plymouth – arguably served to ratify their acceptance of this basic arrangement. Indeed, Price affirmed,

By purchasing our goods they paid our taxes; and, by allowing us to regulate their trade in any manner we thought most for our advantage, they enriched our merchants, and helped up to bear our growing burdens. They fought our battles with us. They gloried in their relation to us. All their gains centered among us; and they always spoke of this country and looked to it as their home. 
                       
Though, again, the author of Observations seemed inclined to portray the inhabitants of British America as inherently – some might say excessively – inclined to embrace their status as the distant province of a large and magnificent empire, his core observation remained a valid one.

The colonists had rarely question Britain’s authority, and never effectively threatened it. The British economy, in consequence, had reaped tremendous advantages by its connection with America, and successive governments had been able to oversee periods of growth, prosperity, and even military success as a result. The North Ministry’s campaign, between 1765 and 1775, to further bind the various colonial governments to the will and authority of Parliament could not, therefore, had had anything to do with an unwillingness on the part of the colonists to continue playing their accustomed role as loyal and active subjects of the British Crown. Rather, Price affirmed, it could only have been the result of a senseless, needless, and ultimately destructive need for a greater and greater degree of control. Thus did he write that the British government and people,

Not contended with a degree of power, sufficient to satisfy any reasonable ambition […] have attempted to extend it.—Not contended with drawing from [the colonies] a large revenue indirectly, we have endeavoured to procure one directly by an authoritative seizure; and, in order to gain a pepper-corn in this way, have chosen to hazard millions, acquired by the peaceable intercourse of trade.

The result of such a “Vile policy [,]” Price vehemently asserted, could not be anything but disastrous.

Having come to depend, increasingly, upon the produce and purchasing power of the American colonies, the North Ministry had nevertheless taken such actions as effectively placed precisely these resources beyond the reach of the British state. If the cabal in question had only been contended – had they recognized that what they stood to gain by attempting to bind the colonial governments more closely to the will of Parliament was by no means worth the acrimony that was bound to result – this might not have been the case. They were not contended, of course, and the result was the effective destruction of the goodwill and amity that had substantially persisted between the people and government of Great Britain and their respective counterparts in British America. Indeed, as Price took to characterizing the matter, “Their love is turned into hatred; and their respect for our government into resentment and abhorrence.” And yet, while it would seem exceedingly difficult to somehow reverse this turn of events, it might not have been impossible to do so. Driven by greed and arrogance though the North Ministry arguably had been in its pursuit of greater and greater control over the economies and governments of the various American colonies, it would not have been impossible for them to cease their ill-conceived campaign of domination in the name of restoring that which they had previously endeavored to destroy. All that would have been necessary – injurious to the pride of Lord North and his cabinet though it may well have been – was for the sitting government to request a halt to armed hostilities, petition the Continental Congress for a formal redress of grievances, and approach the resulting negotiations in the spirit of reason, liberality, and good faith. Only then might the actions of the British government have finally matched its rhetoric.

Price was not so naïve as to imagine that this was a particularly likely outcome, of course. If the North Ministry really did desire nothing more than to pursue a program of reform to the Anglo-American relationship without necessarily threatening its integrity – or even if its members had originally sought something more than that but were willing to admit that they had been mistaken – Lord North himself could have (and perhaps should have) called for a ceasefire at any number of opportunities. When news of the first shots having been fired in anger at the Battles of Lexington and Concord arrived in London, for example, he would doubtless have been forgiven by many of his supporters for deciding that it represented the better part of prudence to pull back from the brink. The costly Battle of Bunker Hill would seem to have represented much the same kind of occasion, or the beginning of the Siege of Boston, or the American invasion of British Quebec. That the North Ministry chose not to avail itself of these chances, however, and that it instead determined with even greater vehemence to achieve the armed pacification of America, seemed to affirm Price’s steadfast belief that it was a lust for power rather than any need for closer commercial ties that had motivated and continued to motivate the sitting government of Great Britain.

Far from emerging from their defeat at the hands of British arms wielded by British hands eager and able to offer the victorious government even greater access to their resources and markets, Price in fact asserted that,

The provinces of America, when desolated, will afford no revenue; or if it should, the expence of subduing them and keeping them in subjection will much exceed that revenue.—Not any of the advantages of trade: For it is folly, next to insanity, to think trade can be promoted by impoverishing our customers, and fixing in their minds an everlasting abhorrence of us.

No doubt Price would have said that this was a fairly obvious conclusion to draw. War does not often turn enemies into capable and enthusiastic business partners. That Lord North and his supporters appeared neither to understand this maxim nor heed it thus appeared to demonstrate that the needs of business were not and had never been their concern. Far from seeking, as they claimed, merely to affirm the proper place of the American colonies within the larger context of Britain’s global financial empire, they rather endeavored to gratify their collective ego and sooth their wounded pride by forcing the complete subjugation of that distant population who dared to assert that their liberties were beyond the power of Parliament to affect.