Friday, June 4, 2021

The Purpose and Powers of the Senate, Part II: The Lordly Ones

    Before delving into the specific discussions that took place during the Philadelphia Convention (1787) whose ultimate product was the United States Senate, it would first seem to bear examining certain of the philosophical assumptions that the Framers brought to the debates. If one is to understand why the men who authored the Constitution felt it necessary to craft an upper house possessed of certain specific prerogatives, after all, one should really start by examining some of the comparable institutions which existed within the 18th century Anglo-American political tradition. Most of the Thirteen Colonies, for example, possessed legislative assemblies with an appointed upper house, the existence of which doubtless helped to condition how the various individual Framers thought about political power and its connection to social prestige. Just so, existing at that same time either alongside or above the colonial assemblies – depending on who was asked and when – was the British Parliament itself, possessed of a hereditary upper house as well as an elected lower one. None of the colonial governments contained anything all that similar to the British House of Lords, of course, particularly in terms of the latter’s composition and responsibilities. But it is obvious enough, when one compares the basic frameworks of the various colonial administrations with that of the government of Great Britain, that the inhabitants of 17th and 18th century British America were broadly intent on recreating as much of the British style of government as they possibly could manage. America might not have been home to a landed aristocracy on the same order as was contemporary Britain, but the American colonists – or perhaps just the political classes therein – nevertheless seemed to hold to certain aristocratic assumptions about authority and who should wield it. Since the Framers, to a man, had been raised and educated either within the British political sphere itself or in an American facsimile thereof, it would accordingly seem to bear discussing the nature of both the 18th century British House of Lords as well as its various colonial American counterparts.

    As it existed in the 1770s and 1780s, of course, the House of Lords was substantially more powerful that it would later become. Indeed, with the exception of the period preceding and immediately following the events of the English Civil War (1642-1651), the House of Lords was by far the more powerful of the two chambers of Parliament from the time of its creation sometime in the 13th century until the beginning of its gradual diminution in the early 1830s. Prime Ministers during this period often came from the Lords – the last “commoner” to hold the office as of the 1770s was George Grenville (1712-1770) between 1763 and 1765 – and the body possessed a number of responsibilities which have since been stripped away. With the exception of “money bills” that levied taxes – responsibility for which had been informally vested in the Commons by the end of the 17th century – the Lords could both originate and reject any species of legislation. On more than one occasion, this latter prerogative nearly led to the dismissal of highly consequential matters of policy, with perhaps the most notable example being the Treaty of Utrecht (1713). Negotiated in an attempt to settle the costly War of the Spanish Succession (1701-1714), the treaty was opposed by the vehemently ani-French Whigs who then controlled the upper house of Parliament for what they perceived as its undue leniency towards the soon-to-be-defeated Kingdom of France. The newly-elected government of Tory leader Robert Harley (1661-1724) reacted to this potential scuttling of its desired peace initiative by coming to an agreement with Queen Anne (1665-1714) – who was of like mind that the war had gone on long enough – to create a dozen new Tory peers so as to overwhelm the recalcitrant Whigs. But while the ploy succeeded, setting the pattern for future confrontations between the Commons and the Lords, both the authority and the right of the upper house to reject legislation would remain fundamentally unquestioned for almost two centuries further.

    The other major power still claimed by the House of Lords in the 18th century – that of hearing cases at law – in many ways spoke to its earliest origins as an outgrowth of the English Royal Court. Following the Norman Conquest of 1066, the kings of the House of Normandy established a system of administration known as the curia regis. A kind of council comprised of the king’s officers of state, high clerics, and the landed magnates of the realm, the curia regis essentially served as the king’s government, hearing petitions, dispensing justice, levying taxes, and fielding diplomatic entreaties, all as the situation required. Over time and in response to any number of factors, the curia began to fracture and evolve into a number of more specialized institutions, among them the Exchequer, the Courts of Chancery, the Privy Council, and the Cabinet. One of these institutions, of course, was Parliament, formed out of the larger version of the curia which included both members of the landed gentry and representatives of the various borough and counties. But while the upper house of this new, more specialized body no longer laid claim to all of the responsibilities that had fallen to the curia, it did maintain certain of the judicial functions that had previously belonged to its predecessor. Specifically, as the various lower courts were established to hear cases that belonged to increasingly specialized branches of English and British law, the House of Lords adopted the role of the Kingdom’s court of last resort.

    The exact nature of this responsibility was one that developed over time. Initially, within the context of its functional authority as the highest court in the land, the Lords would accept submissions from petitioners, vote on whether to reject them or hear them, and then send those that they accepted to be considered by a specially formed committee. Over time, this committee gained the ability to accept or reject petitions on its own authority while the actual number of submissions fluctuated significantly. Between the beginnings of the 16th century and the 17th century, the number of cases heard by the Lords declined precipitously, only to then increase once more beginning in the 1620s. By the end of the 1660s, as a result of a dispute between the Lords and the Commons over the limits of the latter’s judicial jurisdiction, the Lords finally lost the ability to hear submissions directly and instead adopted the practice of taking cases strictly on appeal. While further conflicts between Parliament’s upper and lower houses over the nature of the former’s judicial responsibilities would continue to take place over the century that followed, this nevertheless marked the final major alteration thereto until at least the 1870s. The union of Scotland and England into the Kingdom of Great Britain in 1707 for a time seemed as though it might create a gap in the Lord’s jurisdiction by disallowing it from hearing cases previously decided in the established Scottish courts, but by as soon as 1708 this had been resolved in the Lords’ favor. It was accordingly the case, by the middle of the 18th century, that the House of Lords functioned as the final appellate court for the whole of Great Britain and was thus capable of ruling finally and decisively upon virtually any subject encompassed by British law.

    From the perspective of the 21st century, of course, the notion that an assortment of otherwise unqualified aristocrats might possess the authority to deliver a final ruling upon any matter of law is apt to be cause for confusion. How were these men supposed to come to a decision if they were not required to be versed in the law? And from what source did they derive the essential right – unelected as they were – to decide upon cases effecting potentially millions of people? For at least a partial answer to these questions, one might reasonably turn to Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), the English philosopher and polymath who famously articulated an early example of the “social contract” theory of politics in his 1651 treatise, Leviathan. Published in the aftermath of the English Civil War, Leviathan strongly reflected Hobbes’s royalist leanings and his firm belief in absolute monarchy by seeking to articulate a logical justification for the same that had little to do with claims of “divine right.” The rationale underpinning the judicial authority of the House of Lords was not particularly significant to the resulting thesis, to be sure, but Hobbes nevertheless did give voice to certain of his observations on that subject. He opined, for example, in Chapter XXVII of Part II, that while 

The Lords of Parlament in England were Judges, and most difficult causes have been heard and determined by them; yet few of them were much versed in the study of the Lawes, and fewer had made profession of them: and though they consulted with Lawyers, that were appointed to be present there for that purpose; yet they alone had the authority of giving Sentence.

In spite of their seeming incapacity to properly hear the cases brought before them, however, Hobbes nevertheless considered the Lords no less adequate to rule upon matters of law or equity than a were jury of common men. One did not need to be great scholar of the law to capably interpret it, he explained, for those who are responsible for making a final ruling need only be made aware of the facts of the case as supplied by the witnesses and the facts of the law as supplied by the advocates. “In the ordinary trialls of Right,” he thus explained,

Twelve men of the common People, are the Judges, and give Sentence, not onely of the Fact, but of the Right; and pronounce simply for the Complaynant, or for the Defendant; that is to say, are Judges not onely of the Fact, but also of the Right: and in a question of crime, not onely determine whether done, or not done; but also whether it be Murder, Homicide, Felony, Assault, and the like, which are determinations of Law: but because they are not supposed to know the Law of themselves, there is one that hath Authority to enforme them of it, in the particular case they are to Judge of.

    Hobbes not only believed that the Lords were competent to hear and rule upon cases at law, of course. He also held that it was right for them to do so. The reason for this, in essence, was that landed peerage of the Kingdom of England – and later that of the Kingdom of Great Britain – occupied a unique legal sphere fundamentally separate from that of the common subjects of the same. The aristocracy, along with the Crown, were the principal holders of property across the length and breadth of the kingdom. In consequence, while petitions which exclusively involved the persons or property of commoners could reasonably be heard within the confines of local, civil courts wherein the deciding juries were composed of commoners in turn, any petition whose resolution was bound to touch upon or otherwise affect the property or prerogatives of the landed peerage was required to be heard by the appropriate class of adjudicators. Only then, Hobbes explained in Chapter XXIII of Part II, “Having his own Judges, there could be nothing alledged by the party, why the sentence should not be final [.] It would have been improper to dispense justice otherwise, to allow commoners to rule upon persons who were manifestly not their peers. And since nearly every law which was approved by the House of Commons was bound to exert some manner of effect upon either the persons or the property of the landed peerage of the kingdom, it made perfect sense that the Lords should possess the final word on all such matters whatsoever.   

    Naturally, this constitutes a fairly classist reading of the nature of law and equity wherein the notion of “peer” – in terms of one who is fit to stand in judgement of another – has been substantially warped to encompass broader material considerations. A commoner, in Hobbes’s estimation, could never be the peer of an earl or a viscount, if for no other reason than their interests were bound to be vastly unalike. Indeed, a viscount might be said to exist as something more than just a particularly wealthy individual, for they do not own their estate in the same way that a wealthy commoner might claim to do. On the contrary, the property whose use they enjoy is something which exists separately from either their use of it or their family claim to it. Politically speaking, it forms a part of the administrative organization of the larger kingdom itself, and in the event that a viscount dies without heirs, their title and their lands will accordingly revert back to the Crown. The Crown might decide to grant that same title again, and it might remain with the lineage in question for centuries thereafter, but it will still always revert back upon extinction. All of this would seem to place aristocratic property and aristocratic personages in something broadly overlapping both public and private categories of law. The House of Lords might thus be said to represent as much the interests of a particular class of people as the interests of the landed estates of which the kingdom is comprised. They are the trustees of the Crown, in a sense, and while it stands to reason that their legislative authority should be exercised in lieu of the Crown, their judicial authority embodies something more like a mix between the public interests of their estates and their own private interests – and rights – as individuals.

    Bearing in mind the influence that such an arrangement of interest was bound to exert upon the assumptions and priorities of the Framers of the Constitution – the lot of them being students of Britain’s contemporary political culture – it also warrants examining the various ways in which the governments of the Thirteen Colonies sought to replicate, reject, or otherwise address the same policy areas that the House of Lords claimed for itself. While there were no landed titles in British America representing grants of favor by the Crown, there were those families whose wealth, extent of property, and social pretensions placed them in the same relative social category as the aristocracy of contemporary Britain. And there was also, within almost all of the colonial governments, some kind of hybridized administrative body which formed a bridge between the legislative prerogatives of the relevant colonial assembly and the executive prerogatives of the relevant colonial governor. But while the scions of these various pseudo-aristocratic families did often hold a monopoly on the membership of these colonial upper houses, the resulting socio-political arrangement was not quite an exact mirror of that of the contemporary House of Lords. For one thing, the membership of the colonial “executive councils” was never formally hereditary, its members instead either elected by the colonial lower house or appointed by the Crown on the advice of the governor. And for another, while some of the executive councils did possess judicial responsibilities comparable to those of the British House of Lords, most of them were confined to the legislative and executive spheres.

    Consider, by way of example, the Executive Council of the Province of Massachusetts Bay. By the terms of the Massachusetts Charter of 1691, the Executive Council was to serve as the upper house of the colony’s legislature – the Massachusetts General Court – and as an advisory body to the Crown-appointed governor. Its members – some twenty-eight in number – were to be elected by the lower house of the aforesaid General Court, and their responsibilities were to encompass legislation, judicial and administrative appointments, and, in the event that neither a governor nor lieutenant-governor were available, providing for the administration of the colony as a whole. Prior to the enactment of the 1691 charter, the previous “Council of Assistants” also acted as the colony’s highest court of appeal, but this responsibility was removed when Massachusetts Bay became a Crown Colony at the end of the 17th century. Election to the Executive Council was neither for life nor for a set term; its members rather served “at the pleasure” of the governor. And while landed interests were certainly representing within the Council, the body itself was not tied to any particular estates or jurisdictions. Rather, as it suited the needs of the Crown and its chosen governor, the composition of the Council reflected a mixture of patronage and powerful interests. Granted, the Crown did not have a hand in filling Council seats directly, but it could nevertheless be assured by the fact that it did choose the governor that those who outwardly favored the Crown’s prerogatives would be well-represented therein. In consequence, while the Massachusetts Executive Council almost certainly encompassed a more varied set of perspectives than was present in the contemporary House of Lords – chiefly those of lawyers and merchants – they were nevertheless united by a common sense of affinity with the Sovereign.

    The equivalent institution within the colonial government of Virginia functioned and was structured along very similar lines. The Virginia Council of State was comprised of twelve members who were likewise seated quite irrespective of geography and who were also possessed of both legislative and executive responsibilities. But whereas the members of the Massachusetts Executive Council were elected – pending the consent of the governor – by the lower house of the colonial legislature, the Virginia Council of State was filled strictly by royal appointment. Said appointments were not made by the Crown in isolation, of course; the governor customarily supplied the necessary recommendations. But since the governor was likewise an appointee of the Sovereign, the Council of State was almost exclusively a mechanism of legally sanctioned royal patronage. Membership was accordingly conditioned by both loyalty and wealth. The latter, of course, was the price one paid in exchange for official preferment, while the former functioned as both a symbol of one’s fitness and a guarantee of faithful service. A well-heeled planter, after all, could devote more time to their official duties than an up-and-coming lawyer whose practice demanded a goodly portion of their attention. And since the Virginia Council of State also mimicked the House of Lords by serving as the court of last resort for all cases before the colonial bar, it also made sense for those most invested in colonial society to make the final determination in all matters of colonial law. More than was the case in Massachusetts, therefore, the executive council of the Province of Virginia functioned as the chief organ of the landed interests of that colony.

    While the governing charter of the Province of Pennsylvania – circa 1701 – also made provision for an institutional body with both legislative and executive powers, it rather unsurprisingly deviated from what was otherwise the British American norm. Unlike most of its counterparts in the other colonies, for example, the Pennsylvania Provincial Council was both popularly elected and geographically structured. Every county in Pennsylvania was to send three members to sit on the council, amounting to no less than eighteen and no more than seventy-two in total, and every councilor was to serve for a period of three years. Also, whereas it was the norm in most colonies for the executive council to possess legislative authority in equal measure to the elected colonial assembly, this ceased to be the case in Pennsylvania after 1701. While an earlier charter – enacted in 1683 – stated that,

The Governor and provincial Council shall have the power of preparing and proposing to the Assembly, hereafter mentioned, all bills, which they shall see needful, and that shall, at any time, be past into laws, within the said province and territories thereof [,]

The Frame of Government adopted in 1701 – at the end of a lengthy period of strife between colonial proprietor William Penn (1644-1718) and the inhabitants of the colony he had founded in 1682 – made no mentioned whatsoever of any legislative authority which the Provincial Council might claim to wield. That body, in consequence, entirely ceased to function as the upper house of the colonial assembly and instead restricted its activities to creating and filling judicial offices, providing advice to the governor, and administering the colony whenever its chief executive was absent. The Provincial Council, in consequence, might be said to represent the most significance deviation from the model embodied by the contemporary House of Lords. It possessed neither legislative nor judicial responsibilities and functioned more like an appendage of the colony’s executive branch than a conventional upper house. And yet, in spite of its comparatively unusual set of prerogatives, the Provincial Council was one of the only institutions of its kind in the colonies that mimicked the House of Lords in terms of the latter’s geographic structure. Councilors were not the rulers of Pennsylvania’s landed estates, to be sure, but they nonetheless shared with their aristocratic opposite numbers a strong sense of regionalism in terms of the counties they represented.

    Granting that a great many things transpired between the beginnings of the American Revolution in the 1760s and 1770s and the creation of the United States Senate during the Philadelphia Convention of 1787 that most assuredly changed how the Framers felt about the very concept of an upper house, it nevertheless warrants examining some of the related assumptions with which these men were raised and educated. They may not have possessed as direct a relationship with the British House of Lords as might have been the case had they been born and lived in Britain proper, but many of the philosophical underpinnings of that selfsame body had been substantially replicated within the various colonial governments that had been established in British America over the course of the 17th and 18th centuries. The Virginia Council of State was not populated exclusively by landed, hereditary aristocrats – formally speaking, at any rate – but it did function as the chief organ of the propertied class within the context of the government of colonial Virginia. Just so, while the Massachusetts Executive Council was an elected body whose members served at pleasure rather than for life, it did still possess the same legislative function as the House of Lords by permitting those individuals most closely affiliated with the Crown to exercise some degree of influence over the making of law. And while the Pennsylvania Provincial Council represented counties rather than semi-private landed estates, it still likely served the purpose of placing – and teaching Pennsylvanians to place – geography and regionalism next to population as one of the key elements of any legitimate framework of government. The Framers would bring to bear concepts and ideas which had little to do with their specific lived experiences, of course, when they gathered in Philadelphia in the spring of 1787 and set to work designing a national government to replace the Articles of Confederation. In some cases, in fact, they would pointedly reject the assumptions represented by House of Lords and its various colonial equivalents. But those assumption would still remain an essential aspect of the discussion in question, and the end product – i.e., the US Senate – would accordingly, in some fashion or another, bear their indelible stamp.

No comments:

Post a Comment