Friday, July 31, 2020

South Carolina Exposition and Protest, Part VIII: Love the Sinner

    Stepping back for a moment to consider exactly what it was John C. Calhoun seemed to take issue with in his Exposition and Protest as concerned the Tariff of 1828 and its effects on the economies of the various states – as well as why his proffered solutions took the shape they did – a pattern of thought begins to emerge which paints a fascinating picture of American states-rights political philosophy as it was beginning to coalesce in the middle of the 19th century. Its basis was very much that of Jeffersonian strict constructionism, its general mood one of deep reverence for the Founders, and its aim to assert the primacy of the states within the framework of the Constitution. Attractive as each of these components may have been, however, emotionally, aesthetically, practically, or philosophically, it isn’t necessarily clear how well they all fitted together. In the final analysis, the South Carolina Exposition and Protest is an argument against the primacy of the federal government over those of the states resulting from the passage of tax legislation which seemed to favor federal priorities over regional concerns. Calhoun, speaking on behalf of his home state, did not like that Congress passed a law which would drastically affect the economy of the Palmetto State. He did not like that South Carolina was outvoted on the measure in the House and the Senate and must simply accept what came next. He felt that his home state should not be so totally bound to the dictates of federal institutions, and that its sovereignty should entitle it to refuse cooperation. All of this was fair enough, and far from unreasonable as the basis for larger conversation as to the nature of the United States and whom it was supposed to serve. But as soon as Calhoun started to invoke the Constitution and the Founders while arguing in favor of the rights of the states, things started to get…messy…   

    Taking him at his word – and so discounting the potentially disillusioning effects of having worked alternately against and alongside figures like James Madison and James Monroe in the 1810s and 1820s – John C. Calhoun was among the majority of his fellow Americans who, by the beginning of the 1830s, had come to view the Founding Generation as something more than a cohort of particularly impressive human beings. “They were, in truth, no ordinary men [,]” he thus exclaimed in his Exposition and Protest. “They were wise and practical statesmen, enlightened by history and their own enlarged experience, acquired in conducting our country through a most important revolution; and understood profoundly the nature of man and of government.” Earlier in the same document, speaking of the supposed inability of the Constitution to ameliorate the competing interests of the federal government and the state governments, he spoke in similarly glowing terms. “The framers of our Constitution have not exposed themselves to the imputation of such weakness,” he asserted. “When their work is fairly examined, it will be found that they have provided, with admirable skill, the most effective remedy [.]” Clearly, regardless of what he had come to know from personal experience, Calhoun was simply not prepared to countenance any species of attack upon the Founding Generation. The Constitution, being the product of this selfsame cohort, appeared to enjoy a similarly sacrosanct position in Calhoun’s moral universe; it was perfect, ideal, unquestionable. And while its various provisions were certainly vulnerable to misinterpretation – how else could such detestable statutes as the Tariff of 1828 have been passed? – they could not ever be wrong in themselves. This mindset, as it happens, is where the problem seems to originate.

    Notwithstanding his protestations to the contrary, most of what Calhoun actually seemed to take issue with as concerned the Tariff of 1828 – and which he called explicit attention to in his Exposition and Protest – was rooted in the text of the Constitution itself. He argued, for example, that the imposition by Congress of a protective tariff was unconstitutional because its aim fell well outside the scope of the taxing powers granted to that body. “The third section of the first article of the Constitution authorizes Congress to lay and collect an impost duty,” he admitted, “But it is granted as a tax power for the sole purpose of revenue, a power in its nature essentially different from that of imposing protective or prohibitory duties.” The Tariff of 1828, therefore, represented an unconstitutional application of the taxing power of Congress and should rightfully have been voided. Doubtless this seemed a convincing enough argument to Calhoun and his allies. In point of fact, however, there were more than a few things wrong with it. Putting aside the fact that the taxing authority in question is spelled out in Section 8 or Article I rather than Section 3 of Article I – an error quite possibly the consequence of a poor transcription – the text in question does not actually say what Calhoun claimed. As cited above, the author of the South Carolina Exposition and Protest attributed the unenforceability of a protective tariff to the fact that the taxing power of Congress, “Is granted as a tax power for the sole purpose of revenue [.]” In truth, the clause in question only states that, “The Congress shall have Power To lay and collect Taxes, Duties, Imposts and Excises [.]” There are no accompanying caveats, no restrictions as to the permitted nature or purpose of levies, and no other clauses serve to narrow its scope. Indeed, no mention is even made of the work “revenue” in the whole of Section 8.

    Whether Calhoun was aware of these facts or not would be difficult to say for certain. In either case, he most definitely behaved as though he had no knowledge of them whatsoever. Effectively summarizing his position a little later in the same paragraph of his Exposition and Protest, he stated accordingly that,

The Constitution grants to Congress the power of imposing a duty on imports for revenue, which power is abused by being converted into an instrument of rearing up the industry of one section of the country on the ruins of another. The violation, then, consists in using a power granted for one object to advance another, and that by the sacrifice of the original object.

Two more facts, plainly observable to any literate person in 1828, would seem to further disprove the substance of this position. First, the very same section of the Constitution which Calhoun attempted to claim prevented Congress from levying taxes for any purpose other than the generation of revenue – which, again, it does not – also authorizes that selfsame body, “To regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes [.]” Even if Calhoun had been correct in his assertion that Congress did not possess the power to lay taxes for the purpose of promoting certain domestic industries – which, again, he was not – this “Commerce Clause” would seem to authorize it anyway. What else is the legislative protection of domestic industry from foreign competition but the regulation of commerce with foreign nations? How else would one describe a mechanism for promoting the purchase of domestically produced goods over their foreign equivalents than as a tool for regulating commerce among the several states?

    The clause is vague, to be sure, and does not explicitly authorize the deployment of import duties for the purposes intended by the Tariff of 1828. Nonetheless, the Supreme Court – bringing us to our second relevant fact – had already ruled that this vagueness need not have been construed as a limitation. On the contrary, the Marshall Court declared in its finding in Gibbons v. Ogden (1824) that the authority of Congress to regulate commerce was a broad or as narrow as that selfsame body needed it to be. “If, as has always been understood,” the Court ruled,  

The sovereignty of Congress, though limited to specified objects, is plenary as to those objects, the power over commerce with foreign nations and among the several states is vested in Congress as absolutely as it would be in a single government, having in its constitution the same restrictions on the exercise of the power as are found in the Constitution of the United States. 

According to this interpretation of the Commerce Clause, Congress – having “plenary,” or unlimited, authority over the objects within its explicit sphere – could define for itself what constituted interstate or foreign commerce and which regulations were needful or permissible. Calhoun, of course, might have disagreed with this ruling. Indeed, it seems likely that he did. But by his own admission, he was inclined to recognize it. Responding to a rhetorical question as to the possibility of conflict between the laws of the United States and the Constitution, he accordingly noted in his Exposition and Protest that, “A remedy may be found in the power of the courts to declare the law unconstitutional in such cases as may be brought before them.” One imagined he would not have made such a statement if he did not believe it to be true.

    And then, of course, there was the whole issue of the so-called “Supremacy Clause.” As aforementioned, the passage in question is to be found in Article VI of the Constitution and states very plainly that,

This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any state to the Contrary notwithstanding.

That Calhoun took issue with the legal implications of this provision should by now be quite obvious. The whole substance of his argument in favor of a supposed state veto grated directly against its affirmation of the supremacy of federal power. Consider, by way of example, what would happen if a state constitution declared that the state in question was sovereign and autonomous and entitled to act in whatever way its citizens authorized and then a federal judge ruled – for whatever reason – that this was all well and good as long as the state government in question didn’t violate federal law. A strict adherence to the Constitution would seem to mandate absolute compliance. A federal judge had ruled, after all, and the rulings of federal judges were superior to, “Any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any state [.]” Adamant though Calhoun was that, “The only safe rule is the Constitution itself,” it is hard to imagine that he would ever accept such an outcome. He believed – and argued, and asserted, and declared – that the states were sovereign, that their sovereignty had not been fundamentally diminished by the creation of a national government under the Constitution, and that they were accordingly entitled to independently evaluate federal statutes and nullify them at their own discretion. As the existence of the Supremacy Clause seemed to defy this conception of state autonomy, so Calhoun seemed content to act as though it didn’t exist.

    Indeed, this seemed to be his strategy overall. His convictions were what they were. He believed in the primacy of the states and the fundamentally limited nature of the federal government. He thought that it was improper for federal legislation to lend any state or group of states any kind of advantage over the others, and he held fast to the notion that federal legislation could be invalidated at the state level. On their own, these were all perfectly reasonable positions. Coupled to the further conviction that the only legitimate reading of the Constitution is a close reading, however, and the whole lot ceased to make sense. The text of Article I, Section 8 plainly contradicted his stated claims as to the powers at the disposal of Congress. As did a recent ruling of the Supreme Court, whose authority he claimed to recognize. As did the text of Article VI, which almost completely invalidated his core premise. And what was Calhoun’s response? He had none. He didn’t engage with the provisions of the Constitution which seemed to contradict his established claims; he didn’t explain how it was that the sovereignty of the states entitled them to powers that were not described in the United States Constitution; he didn’t take the trouble to clarify how the powers and restrictions he described could be rooted in texts that said either nothing of the sort or the exact opposite. On the contrary, his plan seemed to be to simply ignore anything and everything that didn’t speak to his position. His convictions were what they were, and the Constitution agreed with him, and that’s all there was to it.

    What’s so mystifying about all of this is how much easier Calhoun could arguably have made things for himself if he had just dropped the whole idea that the Constitution was sacrosanct. Doubtless he felt that this was not something he could do, that there was too much to gain by claiming the legacy of Jeffersonian strict constructionism and too much to lose by trying push against the popular habit of lionizing the Founders and their works. Perhaps there was something to the latter concern. Perhaps he would not have been near so influential had he openly attacked the Constitution as an imperfect document in need of thorough revision. But it was certainly possible to be a strict constructionist and an ardent supporter of the rights of the states. Thomas Jefferson had been just that. His belief in the ability of the states to nullify federal law was as misplaced as Calhoun’s, but at least he was consistent in what it was he chose to attack. The Sedition Act (1798), to which Jefferson’s Kentucky Resolutions was partly written in opposition, did indeed take liberties with the plain text of the Constitution. By making it a crime punishable by, “A fine not exceeding two thousand dollars, and by imprisonment not exceeding two years [,]” to, “Write, print, utter or publish […] any false, scandalous and malicious writing or writings against the government of the United States, or either house of the Congress of the United States, or the President of the United States [,] Congress has indeed plainly violated the terms of the First Amendment. That Jefferson’s solution to this misdeed was also unconstitutional certainly didn’t help his case, but at the very least he could not be charged with drawing attention to something that did not in the least bit warrant it. John C. Calhoun was not so fortunate.

    In fairness, the author of the South Carolina Exposition and Protest did not have all of the advantages in 1828 that Thomas Jefferson enjoyed some thirty years prior. Or, perhaps more to the point, he did not have one crucial advantage. Jefferson, though he self-consciously identified himself as a strict constructionist who believed that the plain text of the Constitution was the only valid guide to what federal government could or could not achieve, was also a contemporary of the fifty-odd men who originally created it. There were known to him, in all their virtues and frailties, and he accordingly seemed to feel no particular need to treat their work as though it was sacred. It was a useful thing they had constructed, potentially, particularly if one adhered to its provisions very closely, but it was far from perfect. If he felt it needed modification, he would not hesitate to say so. And if he could lend his efforts to an attempt at modification, he would do so. Calhoun, notwithstanding what he actually seemed to think about the Constitution, was not nearly so free to say and to do as he pleased. He had adopted the same basic approach to constitutional interpretation that Jefferson had pioneered, but at a different time and for different reasons. No doubt he also believed, as the Sage of Monticello had before him, that a close reading of the Constitution was the best way to ensure that American liberties were preserved. But having also come of age during a time when the Founders of his nation were being swiftly elevated to a kind of socio-political godhood, it was almost inevitable that Calhoun would come to understand the Constitution on very different grounds than the aforementioned Jefferson.

    If John C. Calhoun had been honest with himself, he might simply have argued that the implications of the Tariff of 1828 were cause to both reexamine certain provisions of the United States Constitution and to consider certain amendments as it was determined they were required. Plainly, this is what he wanted to do, what he wished he could do. But in actual fact he either could not or would not. Maybe this was the result of a purely strategic consideration. Notwithstanding his own decidedly mixed experiences working against and alongside members of the Founding Generation, maybe he was nonetheless forced to conclude that the larger share of his countrymen would dismiss him out of hand if he dared to cast aspersions upon the efforts of their secular saints. And then again, maybe it was as important to Calhoun personally that the Framers remain untouched and untouchable as it was to his countrymen who acclaimed George Washington as the Father of the Nation and heralded James Madison as the Father of the Constitution. In either case, the result would have been the same. None of this is to say, mind, that there is anything wrong with arguing for the rights of the states. Nor, indeed, is there anything fundamentally the matter with believing in the efficacy of strict constructionism. It's just that these two strands of argument have so often been combined – in the 19th century, in the 20th century, and as frequently, now, in the 21st century. And it just that the combination tends to be something of a self-negating muddle.

            Am I wrong? Am I missing something? You tell me.

No comments:

Post a Comment