Friday, September 28, 2018

Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, Part VI: Illogical, Unthinking, Hypocritical Britain

            Having gone to significant lengths in the text of Part I of his Observations to lay out precisely what it was he understood of liberty in practice – with pervasive reference to the program of the 17th century Country Party – Richard Price thereafter proceeded to examine the facts of contemporary British government policy in the empire’s restive American dependencies. At the time that he was writing, it would do well to recall, the Thirteen Colonies were effectively in a state of war with their nominal European overlord as though they were a nation unto themselves. The colonies, in addition to maintaining their traditional legislatures and governors, were at least partially under the authority of a series of revolutionary congresses, none of which recognized the authority of the sitting British government. These “provincial congresses,” in turn, sent delegates to a Continental Congress in Philadelphia whose leadership sought alternately to direct an ongoing military conflict with Britain and pursue a peaceful settlement with the same. Battles had been waged – principally in Massachusetts – the British occupation of Boston had largely been stymied, and an American invasion of Quebec had been launched and defeated, all by the end of 1775. It had been, in short, an eventful year.

As the sun rose on 1776, however, the colonies had yet to take the step of declaring their independence from Great Britain. In spite of everything that had occurred thus far – the blood that was shed, the vitriol spewed forth – Congress and the North Ministry were united in their common desire for a settlement of the dispute and a return – more or less – to the status quo. The Thirteen Colonies, it seemed, for all the grievances their citizens nurtured against successive British governments, in large part maintained that continued union with Great Britain was in their collective best interest. Just so, notwithstanding the degree to which certain colonists and their governments had defied the authority of Parliament and the Crown, the government of Lord North (1732-1792) was no less convinced that Britain stood to benefit economically, strategically, and diplomatically from America’s continued inclusion within the larger British Empire. Bearing this shared conviction in mind, however, and exploring all the ways in which the North Ministry and certain of its predecessor sought to pursue it, Price was forced to note a rather curious state of affairs. Long though successive British governments had claimed to value America, it resources, and its people, and adamant though the contemporary administration of Lord North was as to the need to defend the principles of the British Constitution in the face of a sustained and systematic challenge, almost nothing that Britain had done or continued to do in the name of preserving its rule in America seemed at all capable of producing that result. On the contrary, Price asserted, it looked as though, beginning in the 1760s, one ministry after another had done everything in its power to alienate people of America, drive the colonists away from any further connection with the British Empire, and violate nearly every constitutional principle that Parliament traditionally claimed to uphold. Whether the result of misapprehension, thoughtlessness, or insincerity, these errors were the reason Price believed the Anglo-American relationship could never be repaired, and also why he seemed increasingly convinced that it was likely preferable this should be the case.

In seeking to advance this argument, Price first set about establishing a few more basic principles on the order of liberty in theory and practice. Namely, he set out to explore – in Part I, Section III of Observations – a subject of particular significance within the context of the Anglo-American relationship, being the validity of one country claiming authority over another. Having already discussed the degree to which he believed liberty was contingent of the possibility for independent action, it very much stood to reason that Price would apply the same logic to the relationship between master and subordinate nations and arrive at the same conclusion. Just as there was – to his thinking – no way to deny a people the ability to reasonably act out their desires without in some way infringing on their liberty, he affirmed that,

It is an immediate and necessary inference that no one community can have any power over the property or legislation of another community, that is not incorporated with it by a just and adequate representation.– Then only, it has been shewn, is a State free, when it is governed by its own will. A country that is subject to the legislature of another country, in which it has no voice, and over which it has no countroul, cannot be said to be governed by its own will. Such a country therefore, is in a state of slavery.

Declining at this stage to name any specific countries, Price’s intention would nonetheless have been hard to mistake. Though they were colonies in point of law, the various governments that then existed in British America were by and large the functional equivalent of independent states. Granting that their various chief executives were most often appointed by the Crown on the advice of the Privy Council, each possessed a legislature and a judiciary that were functionally independent of either Parliament or the various British courts. That these selfsame colonial assemblies undertook to levy taxes upon the communities that elected their members was thus entirely in keeping with the basic principles of the British Constitution and represented precisely the kind of functional autonomy that Price had earlier associated with liberty.

            In the event, however, that Parliament attempted to levy taxes upon these American communities – as they did in 1764, 1765, 1766, and 1773 – the continued existence of liberty became at once doubtful. America did not elect members to sit in the Parliament of Great Britain – i.e. America was not, “Incorporated with [Britain] by a just and adequate representation.” The taxes allocated by that body thus represented something other than the will of the citizens to which they were meant to be applied. By Price’s definition, the various colonies could thus be fairly characterized as countries, “Subject to the legislature of another country, in which [they have] no voice, and over which [they have] no countroul [.]” It followed that America thus “governed” by Britain, “Cannot be said to be governed by its own will [,]” and was in effect existing in a state of slavery. Bearing in mind that slavery was yet still legal in the British Empire, Price’s invocation of the practice was most definitely intended as a critique upon the British Parliament’s treatment of its nominal American constituents. However Price may have felt personally about the practice – and there would seem to be evidence enough to suppose that he was not in favor of it – slavery was not a state to which most contemporary European Christians believed other European Christians deserved to be subjected. Notwithstanding the history of slavery being in large part colorblind, the institution had by the 18th century become highly ethnocentric, with those to whom it continued to apply – i.e. non-European and non-Christian peoples, principally from Africa and Asia – considered spiritually, intellectually, and morally inferior to their civilized overlords. To be a slave, therefore, by the terms of Price’s likely audience, was to be unintelligent, brutish, and unprincipled, and essentially fit for no other life than perpetual servitude.

            This only entailed the contemporary view on individual enslavement, of course. It was Price’s belief that the enslavement of entire nations presented a worse prospect by far because the nature of the resulting master/supplicant dynamic was bound to be even more impersonal. Humiliating though it undoubtedly was, he affirmed accordingly, the enslavement of one individual to another at least presented the opportunity for intimate personal contact, and thus contained the possibility for the development of, “That fellow-feeling that takes place between persons in private life.” The country that found itself enslaved to another was comparatively at a loss to nurture this same potential for sympathy. “Being detached bodies that never see one another,” Price explained, “And residing perhaps in different quarters of the globe, the state that governs cannot be a witness to the sufferings occasioned by its oppressions; or a competent judge of the circumstances and abilities of the people who are governed.” This unfortunate state of affairs was likely to be made more troubling still, Price asserted, by the thoughtlessness inevitably resulting from such an arms-length relationship. Having doubtless taken on the administration of this distant province for the purpose of achieving some benefit for itself, the governing nation would have every reason to strain the resources of the subject nation beyond the point of comfort and possessed no convenient means by which to be made aware of – or pressing need to alleviate – the suffering that would likely result. “The more the one is loaded,” the author of Observations accordingly observed, “The more the other may be eased.” Again, though yet preferring to speak in general rather than specific terms, Price’s aim is not difficult to discern. The effect of the contemporary policy of Parliament to lay taxes upon a people that it did not represent – and for the purpose of paying off a debt to which they did not direct contribute – was to essentially strip them of their liberty without even the benefit of having their suffering accordingly observed.

            Price’s assertions became somewhat more pointed as this train of argument continued. Having put forward an ostensibly hypothetical scenario in which an otherwise free and sovereign state was made subject to the legislative authority of another, distant nation – the result being an inevitable conflict over which body could claim final and legitimate authority – he went on to describe a series of consequences that would have surely appeared strikingly familiar to a contemporary resident of British America. “In order to remedy this evil,” Price proposed,

And to give efficiency to its government, the supreme state will naturally be led to withdraw the Governor, the Council, and the Judges from the controul of the Province, by making them entirely dependent on itself for their pay and continuance in office, as well as for their appointment.

The author of Observations also proposed that this same hypothetical “supreme state” might further assert its control over the comparatively subordinate “Province” by attempting, “Under the pretence of the impossibility of gaining an impartial trial where government is resisted […] ordain, that offenders shall be removed from the Province to be tried within its own territories [,]” and may even go so far as, “Forbidding all meetings and associations of the people, except at such times, and for such particular purposes, as shall be permitted them.” In addition to representing a deplorable state of affairs on the part of the theoretical subject nation – their being left without recourse to justice or the means by which to publicly express their discontent – this series of punitive measures rather closely paralleled the actual policies visited upon British America between 1770 and 1776.

            Though the British sentries arrested and tried for their role in the events of the Boston Massacre (March 5th, 1770) were ultimately acquitted in November of that year – thanks in large part to the defensive counsel of one John Adams (1735-1826) – contemporary British authorities remained skeptical that such an outcome might easily be repeated.  The notion of colonial courts trying British officials at a time when the Anglo-American relationship was experiencing a period of sustained tension evidently gave pause to certain members of the newly-installed government of Lord North (1732-1792). It was thus shortly thereafter proposed – ostensibly in response to complaints on the part of colonial jurists that their salaries were prohibitively low – that the yearly wage of American justices might be increased by transferring the responsibility for payment from the colonial legislatures to the His Majesty’s Treasury. Seeing in this offer an attack upon the independence of the colonial judiciary, all of the justices of the Massachusetts Superior Court of Judicature – with the exception of Chief Justice Peter Oliver (1713-1791) – refused to take part. Shortly thereafter, in response to the so-called Boston Tea Party (December 5th, 1773), the North Ministry attempted again to “protect” British magistrates and officers from the vagaries of American justice as part of a series of punitive measures. The resulting Administration of Justice Act (1774) declared, among other things, that, 

If it shall also appear, to the satisfaction of the said governor, or lieutenant-governor respectively, that an indifferent trial cannot be had within the said province, in that case, it shall and may be lawful for the governor, or lieutenant-governor, to direct, with the advice and consent of the council, that the inquisition, indictment, or appeal, shall be tried in some other of his Majesty's colonies, or in Great Britain [.]

Decried by members of the increasingly animated Massachusetts opposition as the “Murder Act” for the license they believed it would confer upon British officials to commit heinous crimes without fear of being tried by those they had injured, this piece of legislation served only to further threaten the integrity of the Anglo-American relationship. Unable to simply purchase legal impunity, it seemed the North Ministry had instead resolved to establish it by law.

            Evidently conscious of the resentment that such policies would inevitably engender, the government of Lord North also sought and received the passage of the Massachusetts Government Act during the same session of Parliament in the spring of 1774. This additional piece of legislation, like the aforementioned Administration of Justice Act, aimed to both punish the people of Massachusetts for the disrespect they had shown to the authority of Parliament and the Crown as well as prevent any future expression of discontent or disobedience. The act accordingly suspended the charter under which Massachusetts had been governed since 1691, erecting in its place a far more centralized administration wherein the Crown and its chosen Governor exercised unparalleled authority. The elected Executive Council – unique in British America – was replaced by a body to be appointed directly by the Crown, while a number of civil offices also customarily chosen by a college of voters were to be filled on the sole authority of the aforesaid Governor. Where this not draconian enough – serving effectively to isolate the popular, democratic element of the colonial government in the lower house of the legislature – the Massachusetts Government Act also prohibited the calling of town meetings without the consent of the colony’s chief executive.

Representing a form of local government unique to New England and a legislative platform among the most democratic in the contemporary British Empire, the town meeting had been a foundational element of socio-political organization in colonial American since the early 17th century. Not only did the practice allow qualified citizens to freely express their opinions, concerns, or proposals in a space protected by law and tradition from censorship or interference, but it also served to commemorate and reaffirm the Puritan heritage of the Massachusetts Bay Colony and the attendant social values of autonomy, community, and self-discipline. Notwithstanding the accordingly intense social and political significance of the town meeting, the text of the Massachusetts Government Act declared, 

Whereas a great abuse has been made of the power of calling such meetings, and the inhabitants have, contrary to the design of their institution, been misled to treat upon matters of the most general concern, and to pass many dangerous and unwarrantable resolves: for remedy whereof, be it enacted, That from and after the said first day of August, one thousand seven hundred and seventy-four, no meeting shall be called by the select men, or at the request of any number of freeholders of any township, district, or precinct, without the leave of the governor, or, in his absence, of the lieutenant-governor, in writing, expressing the special business of the said meeting [.]

To a great extent, the ability of town residents in colonial Massachusetts to attend to the administration of their communities – provided they met certain basic qualifications – symbolized precisely the kind of liberty Price described in Observations as finding its source and sustenance in the potential for autonomous action. The Massachusetts Government Act effectively foreclosed on this potential by placing an external barrier between the townsperson and their most basic, accessible, and efficacious public institution.

Beholden though town meeting attendees most certainly were to the laws of the colony and the authority of its Governor, they nevertheless maintained the right and the ability to both regulate the government likely to exert the most profound influence upon their daily lives and to speak freely within that same forum without fear of repression or punishment. Robbing these same citizens of the right to elect members of the Massachusetts Legislative Council – among other offices – undeniably represented a drastic reduction of their ability to direct the affairs of the colony in which they resided. But the reduction of the town meeting from a right to a privilege because certain attendees thereof had dared, “To treat upon matters of the most general concern” arguably symbolized a much crueler act of political and civil repression. Forbidden from freely governing the towns and villages from which Massachusetts itself was born – and from exercising control over the only branch of government many of them would ever encounter in the course of their lives – the affected colonists were left almost completely at the mercy of a legislature, a cabinet, and a monarch over which they could exercise no influence beyond which these same authorities deigned to admit. Such an utter and total loss of the liberty they had grown accustomed to thinking of as their birthright was indeed as close to slavery as any contemporary European subject of the British Crown was liable to experience.

And yet this, as Price asserted in his Observations, was not a punishment reserved only for those populations whose crimes against the state were too unspeakable to name. Nor did it have anything to do with the particular social, religious, of ethno-political characteristics of the affected communities. Rather, it was simply a consequence of one state claiming authority over another. Any nation, comprised of any assortment of peoples, located in any corner of the globe would be forced to contend with the same indignities and injustices were it the subject of another. Attempting to drive this point home – and to seemingly tease out the sense of Euro-centrism that was doubtless common among his prospective audience – Price went so far as to affirm that exactly this state of affairs would manifest itself were his own homeland for once in the role of subject rather than master. “Thus will such a Province be exactly in the same state that Britain would be in,” he accordingly declared,

Were our first executive Magistrate, our House of Lords, and our Judges, nothing but the instruments of a foreign democratical power; were our Juries nominated by that power; or were we liable to be transported to a distant country to be tried for offences committed here; and restrained from calling any meetings, consulting about any grievances, or associating for any purpose, except when leave should be given us by a Lord Lieutenant or Viceroy. 

The purpose of this scenario was almost certainly to shake British readers out of their sense of complacency by asking them to imagine what was effectively the unimaginable.

So accustomed had the average British subject more than likely become to thinking of America as some distant appendage of the Empire by rights wholly dependent on and subservient to the sitting government in Westminster, they could easily have digested the events of the Anglo-America crisis up through 1776 without ever once thinking about the practical effects of the policies being implemented on their behalf. Price sought to push through this habitual antipathy by rhetorically transposing the American plight onto Britain proper. Imagine, he asked his countrymen, if Parliament was forced to obey the dictates of another legislature some three thousand miles distant. Imagine Britain’s justices being appointed by a foreign monarch, its Prime Minister subject to dismissal by a council of foreign magistrates. Most galling yet, imagine the British people being unable to meet in any capacity – nationally or regionally, officially or informally – without first consulting the foreign administrator tasked with overseeing their domestic affairs. Could there be any gloss applied to such an arrangement to make it seem fair and just? Could any affirmation of the continued value of liberty and justice excuse the injuries done to the same? Would it make any difference at all to the benighted citizens of Great Britain to know that their overlords were themselves a fair, kind, and freedom-loving people whose own government was grounded upon the protection of certain basic civil rights?

Though Price did not answer on behalf of his fellow Britons, their response would seem easy enough to intuit. Surely, with nary an exception, they would have recoiled at even the idea that British citizens would ever acknowledge any authority save that of Parliament, the ministry, and the Crown. Their liberties were too dear to them, had been bought at too dear a price, and they would doubtless have died before suffering to have them compromised at the behest of some alien authority whose knowledge of affairs in Britain – owing mainly to physical distance – could not be much more than academic at the best of times. In spite of the likelihood of this visceral reaction being elicited, however, British citizens had been complicit in having exactly these measures takes against their countrymen in America since almost the beginning of the colonial project in the early 17th century. Though they prided themselves as a culture on the personal and political freedoms that historical sacrifice had secured for their enjoyment, the average native-born resident of Great Britain more than likely thought nothing at all of depriving people of their own blood, heritage, and tradition of the same fundamental liberties simply because they did not live in Britain proper. It was precisely this quality of hypocrisy that Price hoped to bring to the attention of his readers, particularly by drawing to their attention the degree to which their own sentiments would have been aroused were the circumstances differently applied. “It is certain,” he accordingly asserted, “That this is a state of oppression which no country could endure, and to which it would be vain to expect that any people should submit an hour without an armed force to compel them.” As true as this was in Britain, Price endeavored to demonstrate to his audience that it was just as true in America.

No comments:

Post a Comment