Friday, July 27, 2018

Discourse Concerning Unlimited Submission, Part IV: Philosophy, contd.

            Having thus affirmed the existence of a tripartite relationship between ruler, subject, and God, Mayhew next proceeded to explain what he believed to be the necessary consequence of an imbalance within this system. The crux of the matter, he offered, was that obedience was owed to God before any earthly authority. His grant of ordinance to civil rulers was accordingly conditional upon the understanding that they would heed his commission to govern justly, honestly, and in keeping with the general welfare. Civil authorities, however, were not alone in bearing fealty to God. The subjects of earthly government, while they indeed owed fealty to those duly-constituted authorities as existed in their region, owed an even higher obedience to God himself. When a given civil ruler ceased to exercise the power vested in them with the wellbeing of their subjects in mind, their subjects were therefore absolved of any duty of obedience to the same and in fact were required to oppose and remove said ruler from the position they were no longer qualified to hold. “Not to discontinue our allegiance, in this case,” Mayhew further asserted, “Would be to join with the sovereign in promoting the slavery and misery of that society, the welfare of which, we ourselves, as well as our sovereign, are indispensably obliged to secure and promote, as far as in us lies.” Thus the minister of Boston’s Old West Church laid before his congregation a proposition that was both unusual for its time yet also plainly flowed out of a close reading of scripture. Kings and parliaments, it seemed, were not the only entities upon whom responsibility for the good of society devolved. Every member of that society, in fact, was required by God to pay heed to the wellbeing of the whole, and to take action to preserve that wellbeing when such efforts were not otherwise forthcoming.

            By way of comparison, Locke’s corresponding argument in favor of a right of revolt focused more on the need to protect individual liberty and private property than the overall wellbeing of the community at large. To his thinking, it seemed, society was not something that needed protection so much as it was an instrument of protection itself. The individual was the source of sovereignty, and thus the crucial element in need of defense.  English law tended to be in agreement. Between documents like the Magna Carta (1215), the Petition of Right (1628), and the Bill of Rights (1689), due process guarantees like trial by jury and habeas corpus, the sanctity of private property, the right to bear arms, and safety from excessive fines or punishments considered cruel and unusual had been enshrined into the very fabric of the British Constitution. The concept of individual liberty was thus demonstrably paramount to the English understanding of political power and citizenship by the time Locke offered his theory of conditional legitimacy in 1689. In fairness, Mayhew did not necessarily attempt to discredit this focus on the individual in his 1750 sermon. Indeed, he more than once used the language of traditional English libertarianism to flesh out his argument in favor of justified resistance to civil authority. “For a nation thus abused to arise unanimously,” he so affirmed, “Is not criminal; but a reasonable way of vindicating their liberties and just rights; it is making use of the means, and the only means, which God has put into their power, for mutual and self-defense.” Here, it seemed, as elsewhere, Mayhew understood unlimited submission as being opposed to the “liberties and just rights” of the individual and accordingly described resistance as a form of “self-defense.”

            In the same breath with which he saw fit to affirm the sanctity of the individual, however, Mayhew also exhibited a distinct distrust in the ability of specific persons to behave with justice and moderation when the power to do otherwise was unquestioningly placed in their hands. “If we calmly consider the nature of the thing itself,” he thus offered,

Nothing can well be imagined more directly contrary to common sense, that to suppose that millions of people should be subjected to the arbitrary, precarious pleasure of one single man; (who has naturally no superiority over them in point of authority) so that their estates and every thing which is valuable in life, and even their lives also, shall be absolutely at his disposal, if he happens to be wanton and capricious enough to demand them.

The vocabulary here deployed paints a rather unflattering portrait of the “one single man” in question. By Mayhew’s thinking, it seemed, he was likely to be “arbitrary,” “wanton,” and “capricious,” and given to indulging his pleasures at the behest of those whose lives it was in his power to render infinitely more pleasant. This palpable sense of suspicion and mistrust, it must be said, was likely a natural outgrowth of the Calvinist tendency to emphasize the inherent sinfulness of the human condition and the consequent inability of mankind to resist self-interest. Having emerged from the same social and theological environment that produced fire-and-brimstone preachers  Jonathan Edwards (1703-1758) – whose most famous sermon, it bears mentioning, was entitled Sinners in the Hands of an Angry God – Mayhew was arguably predisposed to see the darker angels of human nature as being generally ascendant. That being said, there was most assuredly also a political component to his evident suspicion of unlimited power in individual hands.

The target of Mayhew’s January 30th sermon, after all, was an observance whose beneficiary – Charles I – famously quarreled with his subjects and his government over the nature and extent of the authority he claimed to possess. And while the principle upon which Charles had attempted to assert his authority – the so-called “divine right” theory of kingship – had long since been discredited in mainstream British political discourse, the continued veneration by members of the contemporary ruling elite of perhaps its greatest champion was doubtless cause for concern among those who feared the erosion of the post-Glorious Revolution status quo. Being thus both opposed to a principle which he likely regarded as socially threatening as well as generally suspicious of the iniquity of the human race, Mayhew accordingly gave voice to his belief that unlimited power was plainly not meant for individuals. “What unprejudiced man can think,” he thus exclaimed,

That God made ALL to be thus subservient to the lawless pleasure and phrenzy of ONE, so that it shall always be a sin to resist him! Nothing but the most plain and express revelation from heaven could make a sober and impartial man believe such a monstrous, unaccountable doctrine, and, indeed, the thing itself, appears so shocking–so out of all proportion, that it may be questioned, whether all the miracles that ever were wrought, could make it credible, that this doctrine really came from GOD.

One may fairly wonder at Mayhew’s evident tendency to perceive humanity as both too sinful to justly govern without limits to its power and too reasonable to swallow the notion of absolute kingship without express revelation from God himself. If mankind was so base and irredeemable as to invalidate the very notion of unlimited authority, how is it that the rejection of the very idea should appear so obvious to another member of this same ill-starred species? The answer, quite simply, was that both characterizations represented different aspects of the same fundamental truth.

            Jonathan Mayhew, remember, was a Congregationalist minister who came of age and was educated during the height of the First Great Awakening. This trans-Atlantic socio-religious movement, sparked by the revivalist preaching of Englishmen like George Whitefield (1714-1770) and John Wesley (1703-1791) and Americans like the aforementioned Jonathan Edwards, encouraged individual believers to pursue an intense personal relationship with their own salvation and seek evidence of conversion through deep and emotional introspection rather than an intellectual grasp of scripture of doctrine. The resulting evangelical outlook emphasized the universality of sin and the centrality of the conversion experience as the twin poles of humanity’s spiritual existence. As it concerned Congregationalism in 1750s Massachusetts, this dual conception of mankind in essence demanded both a pitiless condemnation of sin and an unshakable belief in the promise of salvation. Sinners in the Hands of an Angry God in particular epitomized this sense of contrast. On one hand, its author excoriated humanity as an incurably sinful species doomed to eternal damnation. On the other, he promised deliverance to those who grasped the mercy Christ had offered them by confessing their iniquities and giving themselves over to the will of God. Mayhew’s seemingly contradictory belief in humanity’s depravity and its decency would seem to align very much with this species of religious conviction. While he emphatically acknowledged the lesser qualities in mankind which seemed to disqualify any one person from wielding unlimited authority, his faith the in possibility of salvation led him to simultaneously affirm that there was something in the human spirit that already knew this to be true. By appealing to this quality in his fellow man – manifested in traits like sobriety and impartiality – Mayhew arguably sought to perform the same action in the context of political philosophy that was otherwise his bailiwick in the realm of the soul.

            This kind of fusion of the sacred and the mundane is precisely what makes it so difficult to separate the political from the religious aspects of Mayhew’s Discourse Concerning Unlimited Submission. There seemed to be, in the mind of its author, little difference between one and the other. Civil government, he repeatedly affirmed, was an instrument of God on Earth whose purpose was to preserve and promote justice, security, and peace. Civil rulers were thus God’s ministers and subjects thus his congregants, all of whom were bound in obedience to his will. The cited verses of Romans 13 embodied exactly this concept – or so Mayhew argued at length – while also offering the caveat that legitimacy could only flow from right action in the eyes of God. Failure to behave in accordance with the purpose God had laid down for civil government effectively voided one’s claim to authority and invited the relevant subjects to cast off their earthly allegiance and seek governors more capable of justifying the trust of the Lord. Taking this framework at face value – as that which fundamentally regulated human society – there would seem to be no room at all for the notion of secular government. Interpreting the aforementioned passage from Romans, Mayhew indeed asserted that it made no difference whether the authorities in question acknowledged the existence of God, denied the existence of God, or even avowed the existence of multiple gods. They warranted the blessing of the Almighty – and thus the obedience of their subjects – so long as they acted with justice and integrity towards those in their charge.

            Mayhew was not alone in linking spiritual and terrestrial authority, of course. The impetus for his September 30th sermon, after all, was the continued commemoration of the execution of a secular ruler by the membership and supporters of a particular ecclesiastical hierarchy. The ruler in question, Charles I, had claimed repeatedly and at length that his authority was derived from God and that he owed allegiance to the Lord before any earthly power. His supporters echoed this same assertion, emphasizing in particular the degree to which Charles gave license to leadership of the Church of England to enforce the basic tenets of its faith upon his Non-Conformist subjects. Not only do these assertions appear consistent with the exhortations contained in relevant text of Romans 13, but they seem even to conform to certain of the basic contours of Mayhew’s elaboration thereof. Just as the minister of Boston’s Old West Church asserted that rulers and subjects were alike bound in allegiance to the authority of God above all, Charles and his partisans had declared and affirmed that the king was bound first and foremost in his obedience to God, from whom all legitimate authority derived. Without necessarily disagreeing with the essential logic of this conviction, Mayhew nevertheless found fault with two aspects in particular of the reign and subsequent canonization of Charles I.

The first – and undeniably the most obvious – was that Charles had betrayed the trust placed in him by God by refusing to behave with justice and integrity towards the people he claimed to rule. Certainly the Anglicans among his subjects were likely to have felt that their faith was being well served by the king’s dedication to episcopacy, to the Book of Common Prayer, and to preventing politically active sects like the Puritans from too aggressively agitating for ecclesiastical and social reform. But all those whose faith did not align with the mainstream Anglican confession – a category which included, but was not limited to, Puritans, Presbyterians, Congregationalists, Methodists, Baptists, and Quakers – undeniably suffered at the hands of Charles and his supporters within the Church of England’s hierarchy. When one also accounts for the number of people who were taxed by the Crown without the consent of Parliament during the 1630s, suffered at the hands of the monopolies Charles granted as a means of raising money, or were killed during the Bishops Wars (1639-1640) in Scotland, the Eleven Years’ War (1641-1653) in Ireland, or the Civil War (1642-1651) in England, the sheer quantity of destruction and displeasure that the king’s actions wrought would seem quite obviously to disqualify him or his supporters from claiming to possess the blessing of the Almighty. “Rulers have no authority from God to do mischief,” Mayhew declared, and Charles I was nothing if not a mischievous ruler.      

            The other reason Jonathan Mayhew might have found fault with the martyrdom of Charles I, in spite of otherwise agreeing with the concept of divine sanction for earthly rule, would seem to derive from the nature of the tripartite relationship described above. Earthly authority, as defined in the text of Discourse, rested upon a foundation composed of three essential pillars. Rulers were blessed with power over their fellow man so that they might serve the community in which they resided. Subjects owed their rulers obedience so that government might function as intended. And God supervised the other two, blessing some with power and promising justice and peace to all. Within this framework, rulers were unique in the authority they wielded and the benefits they enjoyed while still being bound in obedience to the will of the Lord himself. Specifically, kings or magistrates thus blessed by God were responsible for the wellbeing of the subjects in their charge. A ruler who failed to heed this duty – by negligence or with intention – thus effectively violated the unspoken contract upon which their authority was based and exposed themselves to whatever fate their actions set in motion.

In all likelihood, Charles I and his supporters would have agreed with this basic formulation. As far as the king was concerned, all of his actions which critics perceived as damaging to the lives and liberties of his subjects had been undertaken in service of what he and his supporters knew in their hearts to be the one true faith in which God’s promise of salvation was made manifest. By thus faithfully serving the Church of England throughout his reign – and, according to Eikon Basilike, suffering martyrdom rather than see its structure or liturgy perverted – Charles had indeed redeemed the trust placed in him by God by attending tirelessly to the spiritual welfare of his many and various subjects. Those who had suffered as a result of these policies – i.e. Non-Conformists – were of no account because their beliefs were false and heretical, their actions misguided and in need of correction, and their opposition to the prerogatives of the Crown baseless and illegitimate. Charles was able to make this claim, of course, because he was God’s appointed minister on earth. His authority stemmed directly from the Lord Almighty, and no individual, community, or even nation of people could interpose themselves between God himself and the head on which he placed the crown.

It was this final conviction – judging by the arguments he put forward in Discourse – that likely most troubled Mayhew. By claiming to rule by an absolute and divine right – and deriving from that supposed right the authority to speak for God on earth – Charles I seemed to have forgotten the very nature of the source of his power. God was supreme over all, ruler and subject alike. He may have ordained – as per the dictates of Romans 13 – that mankind should obey and support the civil rulers under whose authority they found themselves, but these same rulers were equally bound in submission to the Lord. They could not, in consequence, claim an exclusive knowledge of God’s will or an unequalled right to interpret his intentions. God could not thus be bound to human purposes. His connection to mankind was not linear, flowing only through his chosen ministers, but all-encompassing and omnidirectional. God thus reigned over all things, made himself known to whom and by what means he pleased, and always with the intention of improving the lot of his children on Earth. The error committed by Charles I and his supporters, therefore, was fundamentally one of arrogance. They had claimed to know God’s will, exclusively, and refused to admit that his intentions might manifest in those who were not otherwise blessed with terrestrial authority.

This, too, was very much a criticism rooted in Mayhew’s status as a Congregationalist and a student of the First Great Awakening. Being a proponent of congregational autonomy and a critic of clerical hierarchy – as repeatedly affirmed, hinted at, and boldly declared in the text of his September 30th sermon – it would seem inevitable that he would take issue with the notion that any one person or body of people possessed a superior right to decipher or enact the will of God on Earth. A king, in this context, was no better than a priest – “Who has naturally no superiority over them in point of authority” – aspiring to a greater knowledge of the nature of the Lord or the meaning of salvation. Knowledge of God, the Congregationalist credo affirmed, was the equal possession of all mankind regardless of social station or circumstances of birth. Assertions to the contrary, to Mayhew’s thinking, were of the same quality as the decadent ceremoniousness of the Roman Catholic Church – both having as their object, of course, the separation of the love, the light, and the liberty of God from those who needed it most. Thus did the minister of Boston’s Old West Church declare in his 1750 Discourse, that, “The hereditary, indefeasible, divine right of kings, and the doctrine of non-resistance, which is built upon the supposition of such a right, are altogether as fabulous and chimerical, as transubstantiation; or any of the most absurd reveries of ancient or modern visionaries.” No one had a right to know God or claim his blessing in a way that made them superior to their fellow man, Mayhew thereby affirmed, any more than transubstantiation – symbolic of Catholic practice in general and subject to legal discrimination in contemporary Britain – was truly a miracle.      

The widespread turn towards evangelicalism that was spurred by the First Great Awakening likely fed into and intensified this same basic conviction by further championing the connection between God and the individual. Whereas Charles I, the Church of England, and the High Tory supporters of the same represented the “Old Light” sensibilities of hierarchy, authority, and obedience, Mayhew, his congregation, and contemporaries like the aforementioned Jonathan Edwards championed the “New Light” values of sincerity, morality, and self-reflection. For a New Light like Mayhew, therefore, an avowal of direct and absolute knowledge of God would have likely seemed stultifying, narrow, and reactionary. God, as he understood it, did not move through power structures or priests but through people. To deny this was to deny truth and to foreclose on the possibility of salvation. Far from acting solely through his sanctioned magistrates on Earth, the God envisioned by the First Great Awakening was knowable to every human being and expected from each of them an awareness of sin and a dedication to living a moral existence. Thus Mayhew was able to determine that those who rebelled against and ultimately overthrew Charles I had acted justly and in full accord with the intention laid out in Romans 13. People were expected to obey their civil rulers, he reasoned, not simply because it had been declared that they ought to, but because it served to further the objective – i.e. peace, justice, and prosperity on Earth – which they had in common with God. By the same token, however, at the moment that whatever king, prince, or government under which they found themselves ceased to serve this objective, it still fell to them to act in such a way as to fulfill God’s purpose. Even if this meant removing the civil authority in question, the objective and the means of its accomplishment remained the same. 

No comments:

Post a Comment