Friday, November 13, 2015

Letters from a Farmer in Pennsylvania III, Part II: Sensibilities and Values

            One of the most striking aspects of Letter III, indeed one of the chief reasons I chose to feature it here, is the way it very much lays bare the social, political, and moral values of its author. One of the reasons that I began this very series was the desire on my part to develop a deeper understanding of who the Founder Fathers were as human beings. I wanted to know, and to share with others, where these men came from, what they believed, and how they expressed themselves, and I wanted to contemplate what all of those things could tell me about what kind of people created the strange and beautiful land we know as the U.S. of A. Some of the documents they left behind reveal a great deal. Some are deeply infused with the personal sensibilities of Jefferson, Madison, Washington, and Hamilton, and so act as unparalleled windows into their minds, their emotions, and even their flaws. Others are somewhat more opaque. Marbury v. Madison, undeniably important though it is within the history of American jurisprudence, by necessity allows little room for Chief Justice Marshall’s character to shine forth amidst its dry, sensible legalese. Marbury v. Madison was worth discussing for other reasons, but revealing of the personality and sensibilities of perhaps America’s greatest Chief Justice it is not.
   
            The third entry in John Dickinson’s Letters from a Farmer in Pennsylvania is another beast altogether, and a somewhat contradictory one at that. While stylistically very much in keeping with the scholarly mode of debate perfected by such English writers as Thomas Gordon and John Trenchard in their reformist Cato’s Letters (written between 1720 and 1723), it is perhaps among the most personally resonant documents I've yet encountered from a member of the Founding Generation. Within its scant lines and paragraphs Dickinson reveals himself most plainly, whether it was his intention to do so or not. At once formal and sincere, stiff and passionate, Letter III­ reveals in its form and subject the distinct tension at the heart of John Dickinson’s career as an advocate for the cause of American liberty. A lover of Britain and a lover of his native soil, he seemed ever trapped by dual loyalties, pushed and pulled by the seemingly incompatible desire to both uphold the inherited traditions he had come to revere and fight for the rights he knew to be sacred. Letter III encapsulates Dickinson’s attempt to mesh these sensibilities and values, successfully or otherwise, and so presages the rather difficult position he found himself in once the conflict between colonies and Crown spilled over into bloodshed and both sides began to lose their taste for talk.

            But now I'm getting ahead of myself. Not every element of Letter III represents a conflict of interests and sensibilities. Some of the influences that are most prevalent seem to mingle quite harmoniously, and so give insight into how different strands of moral, intellectual, and political philosophy contemporary to the late-18th century shaped the perspective of men like John Dickinson. Two prevailing elements of Dickinson’s character that shine through the text of Letter III are what we shall call his Quaker sensibilities on the one hand, and his attachment to Enlightenment values on the other. The former was doubtless a product of Dickinson’s upbringing and the influence of his family. The Quakers, or Religious Society of Friends, are a famously non-violent sect, and their devotion to avoiding bloodshed at all costs is deeply engrained in the arguments Dickinson offered in Letter III. The latter, meanwhile, was almost certainly owing to his education. The Enlightenment was a multinational, multi-confessional intellectual movement, rooted in the 17th and 18th centuries, that emphasized reason, equality, and liberality as a remedy for the intolerance, superstition, and jealousy that defined centuries of bloodshed in medieval and Renaissance Europe. Dickinson’s calls in Letter III for prudence and equanimity to triumph over impulsiveness and anger are very much in keeping with these philosophical values and the reformist sentiments that inspired them. Though these two distinct intellectual and moral influences are rooted in different traditions, Dickinson attempted to combine them in the text of Letter III in such a way that they might appear as facets of the same core ideal. 

            Now that I look back on it, that probably didn't make a whole lot of sense. Perhaps I should just show you what I mean.

            In the eight paragraph of Letter III Dickinson stated, as a warning against any rash response to the Townshend Acts, that,

The cause of liberty is a cause of too much dignity to be sullied by turbulence and tumult. It ought to be maintained in a manner suitable to her nature. Those who engage in it, should breathe a sedate, yet fervent spirit, animating them to actions of prudence, justice, modesty, bravery, humanity and magnanimity.

This was, in many ways, the thesis of Dickinson’s public life, and in it can be found principles endemic to both the Enlightenment and Quaker traditions. Talk of liberty, for instance, would seem to belong to both. Quakerism is a self-consciously anti-hierarchical system of belief that lays emphasis on the relationship between God and the individual directly rather than through the mediating influence of a church or ministry. Thus inherent to practising the Quaker faith would seem to be the cultivation of individual freedom from arbitrary outside control or direction. The Enlightenment was also greatly concerned with liberty, its foundation in the human spirit, its limits within political society, and the need for its protection. English Enlightenment political philosopher John Locke posited in the late-17th century that the preservation of individual liberty was the reason that complex social organization existed in human culture; man ceded a portion of his liberty to some form of government in return for protection against said liberty’s violation. Thus inherent in the existence of a state or government, in theory, is a core desire to preserve the liberty of the individuals of whom it is composed. Though Quakerism and the Enlightenment didn't necessarily conceive of it in the same way, liberty was still one of the most important values within their respective moral and intellectual frameworks. So it perhaps seemed to Dickinson that the faith in which he had been raised and the philosophy he had imbibed as a young man both preached of the paramount value of liberty to human existence. 

            Liberty was not the only sphere in which Quakerism and the Enlightenment seemed to cross over. Look again to the cited paragraph, and in particular at the values explicitly named. Dickinson believed, if Letter III is any indication, that true guardians of liberty needed to be animated by a sense of, “prudence, justice, modesty, bravery, humanity and magnanimity.” These are certainly lofty ideals to aspire to, and ones which seem quite at home in either Quaker theology or Enlightenment philosophy. Prudence, modesty and humanity seem particularly Quaker, given that sect’s past prizing of plain speech, plain dress, equanimity in behavior, and social justice. Quaker meeting houses are known for their lack or ornamentation and their services for a lack of rigid structure, and members of the American Quaker community were among the most fervent anti-slavery activists of the 19th century. Likewise magnanimity and justice smack of the Enlightenment, which was again a philosophical movement rooted in the reform of human behavior and social organization as a means of preventing bloodshed. Enlightenment scholars and reformers generally regarded disagreements of faith as one of the roots of organized human conflict. Regimes that believed themselves the only purveyor of truth, as in cases of state religious establishments, took a dim view towards potentially threatening religious diversity. Repression and warfare was the common result, the unprecedented brutality of the Thirty Years War (1618-1648) being the most stark example. Tolerance, openness, or perhaps even magnanimity, were the values Enlightenment thinkers came to believe human civilization needed to embrace if further and more-destructive conflict was to be avoided.

            Quakers valued magnanimity as well, and justice. Derisively labelled in their early existence as “levellers,” members of Religious Society of Friends attach no inherent value to social advancement or hierarchy. In the Quaker mindset, to make a broad generalization, all people are fundamentally equal, and so the arbitrary raising up or holding down of individuals or populations represents a contravention of God’s will. Thus when Dickinson spoke of justice in Letter III he could well have meant it in the Quaker sense of desiring to balance the scales of human existence in accord with divine purpose. At the same time, the Enlightenment attached value to concepts like prudence as well, and humanity in particular. One of the great projects of the philosophical Enlightenment was the cultivation of a sense of universalism; that is, a sense that all people are of a common substance, possess a common inherent worth, and are capable of achieving the same common goals. Though most often associated with Europe and its direct sphere of influence, the scope of the Enlightenment was theoretically planet-wide. The scholars, reformers, public servants and philosophers of the Enlightenment regarded their efforts as being directed at all humanity, from the most base to the most exalted. Thus, when Dickinson wrote of a need from his American countrymen to react to British insults with prudence and humanity he may well have meant it in the Enlightenment sense.

            The point, which has hopefully became a little clearer, is that at least some of what Dickinson expressed in Letter III, some of the values he hoped his fellow colonists would endeavor to embody, could easily have been the product of either his moral or philosophical outlook. Indeed it’s likely they represented a blending of both. As Dickinson consciously or unconsciously filtered his scholarly, philosophical understanding of the conflict between Britain and the American colonies, which prized prudence over rash action and embraced a strong sense of humanist empathy, through the lens of his moral sensibility, which abhorred violence and valued humility and self-control, what perhaps emerged was a personal ideology that embraced rational thought, peaceful manners, dignity, sympathy, and righteousness. To Dickinson this was doubtless a harmonious mixture, combining reason and compassion in a way that was mutually reinforcing. Anger, after all, was the enemy of both reason and peace; clear-thinking, and thus problem-solving, could best be accomplished in a state of composure, accompanied by a clear assessment of one’s abilities and of the conflict at hand. This much he stated in the sixteenth paragraph of Letter III, writing that, “Anger produces anger; and differences, that might be accommodated by kind and respectful behavior, may, by imprudence, be enlarged to an incurable rage.” If this rage were permitted to be prolonged, Dickinson continued, it would soon enough cloud the minds of all concerned to the point that the original cause of their conflict would be forgotten, replaced only with greater anger at the memory of past offences and mounting thoughts of revenge. This vicious cycle, once entered, was near impossible to escape from unscathed. The best solution was to simply avoid giving over one’s reason to considerations of violence and conflict, thereby averting needless bloodshed and permitting the unfettered mind to arrive at a resolution.  Not only was this right, in the moral terms that Dickinson understood, but it made sense. Unfortunately, and as he was perhaps aware, not everyone shared John Dickinson’s strong moral aversion to conflict. Though the reformers of the Enlightenment were devoted to avoiding the outbreak of further destructive wars in Europe and abroad, their philosophies not infrequently sanctioned violence and political upheaval in service of preserving certain fundamental rights.

            Look again at some of the words Dickinson used in the above-cited paragraph. Think about some of the ideas he was expressing. Liberty, he asserted, was too dignified an idea to be tainted by calls to violent action. This is an idea very amenable to Quaker sensibilities, liberty being the foundation of an individual expression of faith, but doesn't necessarily square with certain aspects of Enlightenment philosophy that this series has previously explored. Remember John Locke’s social contract theory from Two Treatises of Government? Locke’s innovation, embraced by Thomas Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence, was in describing a “right of revolution” whereby a free people could rightfully overthrow a government that had become abusive or tyrannical. Dry as this might sound, some application to force would seem unavoidable in cases where the tyranny of a government stemmed from its own application of state-sanctioned and directed violence. In this mode, which seemed to be that favored by the majority of the Founders following the Battle of Lexington and Concord in April, 1775, how could liberty be too dignified to be “sullied” by tumult? Was not some form of tumult at times required in order to ensure the preservation of liberty? In the aforementioned paragraph Dickinson also claimed that liberty, “ought to be maintained in a manner suitable to her nature.” As I'm sure that his contemporaries asked of him at some point or another, was not the maintenance of liberty worth sacrificing one’s life for? To this the scion of Poplar Hall  might had agreed, though his moral sensibilities likely would have compelled him to add that it was only in the most extreme cases worth killing for.

            This apparent contradiction between Dickinson’s personal interpretation of the meaning and significance of liberty and that embraced by the majority of his contemporaries is captured clearer still in the eleventh paragraph of Letter III. Therein Dickinson stated that though, “Every government at some time or another fall into wrong measures […] every such measure does not dissolve the obligation between the governors and the governed.” While Locke – and Jefferson, and any number of his fellow revolutionaries – may have agreed that not every error committed by a government at the expense of its citizens was reason enough for revolt, the admonition that Dickinson next deployed would likely have seemed overly permissive of continued abuse. “It is the duty of the governed,” Dickinson implored,

To endeavor to rectify the mistake, and to appease the passion. They have not at first any other right, than to represent their grievances, and to pray for redress, unless an emergency is so pressing as not to allow time for receiving an answer to their applications, which rarely happens. If their applications are disregarded, then that kind of opposition becomes justifiable which can be made without breaking the laws or disturbing the public peace.

Whereas Locke emphasized the right of revolution as a fundamental check against thee emergence of tyranny in government, to the point of it almost becoming a kind of social obligation, Dickinson associated the immediate response to perceived abuses with patience, caution, and reverence for authority. Even in cases of continued government intransigence, which he argued would “rarely happen,” he maintained that the people’s reaction should still be fundamentally lawful and peaceful. Though again it should not be doubted that men like Locke would have agreed with Dickinson’s general desire to avoid bloodshed if at all possible, the extent to which Dickinson preached deference and appeasement would likely have struck them with a degree of distaste.

            It isn't that Dickinson’s strongly-expressed desire to avoid conflict was a value that his fellow Founders were unable to appreciate. They were, by and large, not warlike men. They understood, when push came to shove during the events of April, 1775, that taking up arms against Britain was undertaking from which it would be impossible to escape unscathed. They thus did not enter into war lightly, though they believed it in service of a thoroughly just cause, and remained throughout its prosecution sensible of the suffering the effort to secure American liberty were mingled with. There was, however, something in Dickinson’s tireless devotion to peace at all costs that many of them doubtless found troubling. Avoiding unnecessary conflict, and maintaining a sense of dispassion and reason, were values very much at the core of the gentlemanly and scholarly ideals embraced by most of the Founders regardless of their profession or from which of the colonies they hailed. Yet these were also men who had largely been educated in a distinctly English tradition that placed special attention on traditional rights, their irreducible value, and the need to guard against their abrogation. Peace was a great virtue, they understood, but their nevertheless came a time when it became necessary for a person to stand up and fight for what they believed. From this perspective Dickinson’s adamant calls for humility, non-violence, and absolute respect for the “public peace” would perhaps have seemed overly permissive. Continue to appease corruption, to bow to tyrants, and do nothing more but beg redress and how long would it take for the offenders to become accustomed to their subjects’ leniency? Without a short, sharp shock, could British authorities be depended on to come to their senses and reform the policies that had raised such alarm in the American colonies? Dickinson seemed unwilling to even entertain these questions, so utterly convinced was he that reason could only ever be given free expression when paired with peace and dispassion.

            The lengths to which Dickinson believed this, if Letter III is any indication, extended to a point beyond which might seem possible for someone considered to be among America’s Founding Fathers. In the eighteenth paragraph of Letter III he appeared to sum up his position on the conflict that had emerged between the American colonies and the British Crown. Whereas someone like Thomas Paine might have signed off with the 18th-century equivalent of “George III is a wanker,” or Benjamin Franklin would likely have tossed off an irony-drenched appeal to the enduring wisdom of the British political establishment, Dickinson adopted a very different tack indeed. “We have an excellent prince,” he wrote,

In whose good disposition towards is we can confide. We have a generous, sensible and humane nation, to whom we may apply. They may be deceived. They may, by artful men, be provoked to anger against us. I cannot believe they will be cruel and unjust; or that their anger will be implacable. Let us behave like dutiful children who have received unmerited blows from a beloved parent. Let us complain to our parent; but let our complaints speak at the same time the language of affliction and veneration.     

It would seem difficult, knowing what came next, not to consider Dickinson hopelessly naïve. Yet naïveté was most certainly not what motivated him to put forth a statement such as that quoted above. John Dickinson was not a foolish man, nor was he unacquainted with some of the less virtuous aspects of British political culture. But he was someone, as will be discussed in weeks to come, for whom Britain loomed large as a source of pride, inspiration and affection. And he was also a man who attached a great deal of social and moral value to ideals like patience and forbearance. As the first several paragraphs of Letter III make quite clear he would not have denied for a moment that the policies enacted by the British Parliament in 1767 and aimed at the American colonies represented an imminent threat to the liberties of the citizens thereof. To speak against the same he characterized as a kind of moral obligation, writing in the second paragraph that, “While Divine Providence […] permits my head to think, my lips to speak, and my hands to move, I shall so highly and gratefully value the blessing received as to take care that my silence and inactivity shall not give my implied assent to any act, degrading to my brethren and myself [.]”

    In spite of this apparent enthusiasm, which seems fairly characterized as an expression of Enlightenment activist zeal, Dickinson was seemingly constrained in how far he would be willing to go and what he would be willing to sanction by an ingrained moral revulsion to violence. To the modern reader these two impulses, both evident in Letter III, doubtless seem somewhat contradictory. Yet for Dickinson they were not, or perhaps he simply hoped so. Clearly he believed with great conviction that the injuries visited upon his fellow colonists could not go unanswered, but his suggestion as to the proper response seems so restrained. The right of Britain’s American citizens to representation in the political process, to govern themselves in accordance with British parliamentary tradition, and to enjoy the benefits of trial by jury were all being seriously threatened. Dickinson’s answer to these challenges was to “behave like a dutiful child,” “complain to our parent,” and make use of “the language of affliction and veneration.” Veneration, yet? What was there to venerate in the behavior of the British officials who intended to rob the colonists of their traditional relationship to their governors while claiming an unrestricted right of taxation? What sort of parent deserves the loyalty of their child after they've taken pains to force their offspring to pay for enjoying the security of the familial household? These are questions which many of the Founders were very intent to discuss in the 1760s and 1770s, but which Dickinson seemed reluctant to acknowledge. Perhaps the reason for this stemmed from an inability to truly reconcile the two halves of his philosophical and moral universe, the Enlightenment of his education and the Quakerism of his upbringing. Harmonious though they seemed in many aspects, and in which harmony Dickinson seemed most comfortable, the crises facing the residents of the Thirteen Colonies in the 1760s and 1770s seemed to expose a critical incongruity between the extremes of Quaker pacifism and the Enlightenment’s veneration of natural liberty. This incongruity arguably came to dominate Dickinson’s subsequent career as a revolutionary and early American statesman, and to this day significantly colors how he has been remembered.

No comments:

Post a Comment