In furtherance of
his assertion that the policy of the government of Lord North towards the
Thirteen Colonies – then engaged in a course of armed resistance to British
authority – was inherently at odds with the basic tenets of the British
Constitution, Richard Price next turned his attention in the text of his Observations to both the state of
representative government in Britain and the impermanence of any claim to
national superiority. Of these approaches, it is perhaps worth noting at the
outset that while the former appeared to be of particular significance to Price
– being, as he was, an avowed supporter of Parliamentary reform – both
ultimately led to the same basic conclusion. Eager though he demonstrably was to
promote a more sensible approach to policy on the part of his country’s
administrative elite – to save Britain from itself, as it were – the concluding
paragraphs of Part II, Section I of Observations
begin to reveal a degree of resignation on the part of its author. Through
clearly endeavoring to promote a deeper and more sincere appreciation on the
part of his countrymen for the sovereign rights and liberties ostensibly
guaranteed by the British Constitution, Price nevertheless also appeared to
dread that his efforts would ever amount to the outcome he sought. Having
argued that the North Ministry and its supporters were being illogical in their
conduct towards the American colonies, that they rationale was hollow and
baseless, and that time might easily undo many of their claims, he more than
once appeared to throw up his hands and lament the evident likelihood that none
of these assertions would serve to change British behavior one iota, and that
it was perhaps more sensible to celebrate America’s principled resistance to
Britain than hope that Britain would ever again be capable of rendering this
resistance unnecessary.
Consider, with
this sense of resignation in mind, Price’s aforementioned attempt to dispel any
claims of America’s necessary submission to Great Britain by way of the
contemporary state of parliamentary representation. Seeking to dispel yet
another hypothetical argument on behalf of the government of Lord North, the
author of Observations accordingly
noted that, “The defective state of the representation of this kingdom has been
farther pleaded to prove our right to tax America.
We submit to a parliament that does not represent us, and therefore they
ought.” It was, Price noted, a very strange way of thinking – simultaneously
pragmatic and wholly illogical. “It is saying we want liberty [,]” he thus
marvelled, “And therefore, they ought to want it.” Not only did such a position
appear to suppose that the unrepresentative nature of Britain’s Parliament was
essentially immutable, but it demonstrated a degree of pettiness and
indifference that did not speak well at all of those who gave voice to it.
Indeed, the interpersonal equivalent would seem to be that of an individual in
ill-humor endeavoring to make everyone around then equally miserable for no
other reason than it appears to them unfair that anyone else should be happy if
they cannot feel that way themselves. Truly, it was not a particularly gracious
sentiment, and one which Price would doubtless have affirmed was better pitied
than made cause for a particular course of public policy.
In point of fact, the claim that the
inhabitants of late 18th century Britain labored under a system of
government that was almost comically incapable of actually representing their
needs and interests was most definitely accurate. As discussed previously in
this very series, the constituency boundaries by which Members of Parliament
were elected in the 1770s had by and large been established over the course of
the medieval era on an ad-hoc basis and in accordance with what were then the
major centers of economic activity and population. In consequence, historic ports,
markets, and church towns enjoyed preference over most other communities,
property qualifications were the norm for access to the franchise, and the
specific regulations by which a person was either permitted to vote or
disqualified from voting varied extensively from one jurisdiction to another.
The flaws inherent in this patchwork system of elections were particularly glaring
in regards to the aforementioned pocket boroughs and the mercantile centers
that emerged over the course of the 16th, 17th, and 18th
centuries. The borough of Dunwich, being a prime example of the former, was
once the site of a thriving port in Suffolk whose fortunes gradually declined
following its recognition in Parliament as the sea steadily swallowed the town
itself and reduced its population by the beginning of the 18th
century to something less than five hundred souls. By the beginning of the 19th
century there were only thirty-two recognized electors in Dunwich, fully half
of which were assigned on an election-by-election basis by a pair of local
landholders. On the other end of the spectrum was the county constituency of
Warwickshire, which, in spite of containing the burgeoning industrial city of
Birmingham – whose population in the late 1770s exceeded forty thousand –
registered only a few thousand electors and continued to be dominated by local
landed interests. The significance of these kinds of disparities was that the
voters of an underpopulated constituency – like Dunwich – enjoyed far more
influence over the disposition of Parliament than did their counterparts in an
overpopulated constituency – like Warwickshire. This state of affairs unequivocally
represented a manifest injustice, and one whose ill effects were actively
magnified as the years wore on.
Richard Price would surely have been
the last person to argue with this kind of assessment. Not only was he fully
aware in 1776 of the deplorable state of political representation in his
homeland, but he represented one of the few individuals possessed of
significant social capital who was at that time yet willing to advocate for an
appropriate course of reform. That being said, however, he would also have been
one of the last people to agree with the hypothetical assertion that the
inhabitants of the Thirteen Colonies should not expect to have their own woes
regarding political representation addressed before those of their British
resident counterparts. In this sense Price was perhaps something other than a
nationalist, if that term can be said to apply in the context of the late 18th
century. He was not someone who favored solving British problems first and
foremost to the exclusion of all others. Nor did he seem to draw the same
socio-cultural distinction between residents of Britain proper and the
population of the larger empire that so many of his countrymen seemed to by
default. Owing perhaps to his vocation as a Non-Conformist preacher, his
upbringing on the fringes of mainstream British society, and his evident belief
in Lockean ideas of sovereignty and justice, Richard Price instead seemed to
tend towards the basic conviction that equality before the law was among the
highest values to which any civilization could aspire. In his eyes it
accordingly made no difference whether a person was born and raised in Britain
or had never – and would never – set foot upon its shores; all were entitled to
the same rights, the same liberties, and the same expectation of sensible and
trustworthy government.
Bearing this in mind, it was only
natural that he would have recoiled at the notion that some people were
entitled to the fulfillment of their rights in advance of others. The people of
Britain and the people of America were equally deserving of truly
representative government, and likewise equally entitled to pursue that aim by
whatever means they had at their disposal. If Britain secured this outcome
before their trans-Atlantic brethren, the latter had no call for jealously,
bitterness, or resentment. On the contrary, they should be given instead to
celebrate the realization of a goal to which they themselves attach a great
deal of significance. Just so, if the people of America managed to achieve
something like this same outcome for themselves – by, say, collectively
extricating themselves from the authority of a government in which they were
not represented – their British counterparts should likewise give praise that
their shared goal had been in some measure accomplished in some corner of the
globe. To do otherwise would be plainly hypocritical. And to blame the
inhabitants of colonial America for the iniquities of the contemporary British
Parliament would be senseless and cynical. On the contrary, the author of Observations asked of his countrymen,
“Ought we not rather to wish earnestly, that there may at least be ONE FREE
COUNTRY left upon earth, to which we may fly, when venality, luxury, and vice
had completed the ruin of liberty here?” While this passage hardly speaks to
any hope on Price’s part that his homeland was capable of being saved, it does
powerfully affirm his conviction that liberty was something to which every
human being was equally entitled, and that the creation of a system of
government reflective of this basic truth should rightfully be encouraged in
every quarter rather than understood as an object fit for competition.
The discussion Price saw fit to
devote to the subject of representative government in the text of his Observations, in addition to giving rise
to the commentary cited above, also served to introduce an idea which
subsequent passages of that selfsame document would shortly explore in greater
depth. Specifically, it was the notion that the goal being then pursued by the
American insurrectionaries – i.e. a government which respected their basic
rights and liberties – represented nothing more or less than the embodiment of
the values embedded in the British Constitution. The inhabitants of the
Thirteen Colonies, the relevant text affirmed, did not want more for themselves
than what any British person would have claimed as their birthright, in no
small part because both Britain and British America recognized the same
socio-cultural touchstones and promoted the same political values. It
accordingly represented a shameful pretense to claim that the American attempt
to resist efforts intended to bring the colonies to heel constituted anything
even remotely close to treason. If the members of the North Ministry and their
supporters could not see this, it was perhaps because they had not considered
the significance of their various policy initiatives from the perspective of
the liberties they themselves would surely have claimed to cherish and uphold.
Consider, to that end, a scenario
Price offered his readers in one of the last paragraphs of Part II, Section I
of Observations. “Britain is now,” he allowed – though
perhaps, in hindsight, without much conviction – “The seat of Liberty and
virtue, and its legislature consists of a body of able and independent men, who
govern with wisdom and justice.” Conciliatory though this phrasing might seem
to the position being firmly upheld by his nominal opponents, however, it in
fact represented only the initial premise of substantially more challenging
line of inquiry. “The time may come,” Price thus continued,
When all
will be reversed: When its excellent constitution of government will be
subverted: When pressed by debts and taxes, it will be greedy to draw to itself
an increase in revenue from every distant Province, in order to ease its own
burthens: When the influence of the Crown, strengthened by luxury and an
universal profligacy of manners, will have tainted every heart, broken down
every fence of Liberty, and rendered us a nation of tame and contended vassals:
When a general Election will be
nothing but a general Auction of Boroughs: And when PARLIAMENT, the Grand
Council of the nation, and once the faithful guardian of the state, and a
terror to evil ministers, will be degenerated into a body of Sycophants, dependent and venal, always
ready to confirm any measures; and
little more than a public court for registering royal edicts […] What will, as
that period, be the duty of the Colonies?
Bearing in mind the
various frustrations expressed by Price that have thus far been cited in this
present series, it hardly seems a stretch to infer that the qualifying phrase,
“The time may come” was almost certainly intended as a cover for his belief
that in fact the time had already come when the disreputable conditions he
thereafter named were actively manifest in the politics and policy of the
contemporary British state. Britain was heavily indebted following its
involvement in the Seven Years War (1754-1763), he explained, and eager to
generate revenue from its American dependencies. Its legislature was wildly
unrepresentative, and subject to chronic electoral corruption. And its
executive government was too easily swayed by moneyed interests, subject to
royal favoritism, and groaning under the weight of an over-inflated bureaucracy.
Having seen these things for himself, however – and marked them out accordingly
– Price was now asking his nominal opponents to consider them in turn.
No comments:
Post a Comment