The next several paragraphs of
Richard Price’s Observations
represented a slight shift in tone from that were preceded them. Whereas Price
had theretofore attempted in Part II, Section I to explore and discount the
various claims made by his countrymen to Britain’s inherent superiority over
the Thirteen Colonies in terms of relative population, wealth, and intellectual
achievement, financial investment, and even by way of the metaphor of the
parent/child relationship, he now endeavored to focus on the logic of certain
fundamental aspects of Britain’s political philosophy and political culture.
Specifically, he asked his fellow Britons to project the implications of their
various assumptions to their furthest extreme and then contrast the result
against the basic constitutional principles by which the contemporary British
state was supposedly governed. If contradictions surfaced as a result of this
exercise – if what Britain was demanding of the inhabitants of America amounted
to more than most British subjects would acquiesce to themselves – then the
validity of the British position could accordingly be called into question.
Price thus evidently attempted to turn the focus of the discussion surrounding
the burgeoning conflict between Great Britain and the Thirteen Colonies away
from what was essentially an accounting of power dynamics and towards an
interrogation of what it was his countrymen actually believed about themselves,
their nation, and their values as a people.
The author of Observations made his entrez
into this more theoretical area of discussion by first investigating the claim
– again, made by the hypothetical supporter of the North Ministry and its
policy towards America – that the colonies were of a right subordinate to
Britain because, “The Land on which they settled was ours.” There appeared to
Price, notwithstanding a number of philosophical questions having to do with
the nature of sovereignty tied up in this kind of claim, several factual errors
present therein. For one, he asserted, the fundamental right of property celebrated
as one of the essential principles of the British Constitution could not easily
be reconciled to the traditional European colonial practice of claiming vast
swaths of land at a distance merely by way of a declaration to that effect. “If
sailing along a coast can give a right to a country,” he mused accordingly,
“Then might the people of Japan
become, as soon as they please, the proprietors of Britain.” This was, of course, a nonsensical scenario, but
purposefully so. Ridiculous as it was to imagine a Japanese vessel sailing up
the Thames in 1776 and laying claim for the Emperor to every square inch of
soil sighted by its crew, Price invited his readers to consider that the
equivalent gesture on the part of 17th century English sailors
exploring the coast of America was no more sensible as a means of establishing
legal ownership over a given plot of land. Real property – in the sense of
landed property – belonged to those who lived upon it, worked it, or improved
it.
This was not a
doctrine, it bears noting, which would have necessarily sat all that well with
the contemporary British gentry or the Anglican Church. Both of these bodies collectively
owned acres upon acres of land that they subsequently rented or leased to those
who themselves made the actual improvements. But it certainly seemed to accord
with Price’s evidently Lockean sensibilities when it came to matters of
sovereignty. Observe, to that end, Price’s further claim in the same paragraph
cited above. “If the land on which the Colonies first settled had any
proprietors,” Price affirmed,
They were
the natives. The greatest part of it they bought of the natives. They have
since cleared and cultivated it; and, without any help from us, converted a
wilderness into fruitful and pleasant fields. It is, therefore, now on a double
account their property; and no power on earth can have any right to disturb
them in the possession of it, or to take from them without their consent, any
part of its produce.
The author of Observations thus demonstrated his
understanding of property rights as being essentially opposed to that expressed
by his hypothetical opponent. Whereas this supposed Northite appeared to
believe that Britain had claimed America for itself by way of some mysterious
right of imperial possession and then sold or rented the land to the various
colonial founders, Price maintained that in fact the region’s indigenous
inhabitants had possessed the original claim to the territory in question and traded
it to the colonists in exchange for whatever money or commodities they
possessed. While the difference between these perceptions might appear somewhat
slight, the contrary is in fact the case.
Price posited a
clear chain of possession from one title-holder to the next – from tribal
polity to migrant community – with deed being transferred via a (theoretically)
consensual procedure. His opponents conversely failed to explain precisely how
the property in question passed into the hands of its American cultivators.
Certainly they had agreed to purchase or rent it from Crown authorities – or
else some agent of the same – but it was not at all clear how they themselves
had come into possession of it initially. Certainly they hadn’t purchased it
from a local authority in exchange for something of equal value, settlement
tending to precede first contact during the formative years of the American
colonial venture. And yet, some ineffable, alchemical process must have taken
place for land that no English person had previously laid eyes on to suddenly
become the possession of the English monarch. Presumably, the relevant
individual(s), acting on behalf of the Crown, had just gazed upon the land from
afar, decided that it should belong to England, and then it did. Impressive
though such a power might have been, however – and certainly convenient for the
monarch who wished to dole out land at will without having to pay for the
privilege – the implications thereof were also nothing short of terrifying.
By entertaining the notion that the Crown was
the original owner of the land upon which the Thirteen Colonies were founded,
one would at the same time be given to tacitly accept that this same authority
– or its agent – could unilaterally claim a given piece of property by way of
simple declaration alone. It did not matter if said property was already in
someone else’s possession – as Price affirmed that the colonial territory was –
and no exchange, discussion, or even notification was necessary. Bearing in
mind that British authorities would very likely have been less inclined to
exercise this privilege upon the property of their own subjects than upon the
property of the non-Christian, non-European indigenous inhabitants of North
America, there was nothing inherent to the principle itself that stood to
prevent the former for occurring. If the Crown could claim property it had
never seen some three thousand miles away with no more than a declaration to
that end, why could it not do the same to the lots and acreages in its own
backyard? How could something as comparatively narrow as property rights stand
against as expansive a power as that? How could the Bill of Rights? How could
any part the British Constitution? That there were no clear answers to these
questions was doubtless in large part why Price tended to oppose the very idea.
Allowing the British government to subvert property rights in certain cases
arguably opened the door for it to subvert property rights in all cases.
Better, then, to demand a clear derivation of authority, a clear chain of
possession, and a clear rationale for intrusions upon individual sovereignty.
There was also, of course, the question of
ownership by way of cultivation. As aforementioned, Price seemed to evince in
the text of his Observations a very
Lockean sensibility in matters of property and its possession. The paragraph
cited above was particularly explicit on this count. Of the land settled by the
American colonists, Price affirmed that, “They have since cleared and
cultivated it; and, without any help from us, converted a wilderness into
fruitful and pleasant fields.” Turning to the relevant text of John Locke
(1632-1704) – i.e. Two Treatises of Government
– one finds much the same explanation for the relationship between labor and
property. “He that so imployed his pains about any of the spontaneous products
of nature,” Locke asserted therein,
As any way
to alter them from the state which nature put them in, by placing any of his
labour on them, did thereby acquire a propriety in them […] The same measures
governed the possession of land too: whatsoever he tilled and reaped, laid up
and made use of, before it spoiled, that was his peculiar right; whatsoever he
enclosed, and could feed, and make use of, the cattle and product was also his.
By thus mixing
one’s labor with what was otherwise common property – by tilling a field,
picking an apple, killing and dressing a deer, or chopping down a tree – the
object in question was made more useful and ownership was transferred from the
commons to the individual. This was, at its heart, a matter of compensation,
whereby productivity was rewarded with the outcome of the same. Consider, to
that end the untilled field. Left fallow, it aides no one; made to sprout
wheat, corn, barley, or buckwheat, however, it could feed any number of people
or animals. In return for accomplishing this transformation – for making
something useless to human society incredibly useful by the expenditure of
certain resources – the laborer takes possession of the value they have
created.
Applied to the context of the
American colonial project, this kind of Lockean analysis would seem to paint
the colonists themselves – who worked the plots and acreages in question – as
the truest owners of their land. However they acquired it – by purchase from
its original indigenous possessors or by grant from the Crown – their efforts
greatly increased its productivity, making it useful in a way that it had not
been previously. And while it was certainly possible for the native peoples whose
land it was originally to have accomplished this same feat of transformative
labor – a number of the indigenous communities then residing in North America
engaged in subsistence agriculture, after all – the likelihood thereof should
form no part of the question at hand. Price did not claim that the ability of
the colonists to improve the land they took possession of gave them a right to
appropriate it from the native peoples they encountered. Indeed, he stated
explicitly of said land that, “The greatest part of it they bought from the
natives [.]” thus obviating any need to establish right or claim. Rather, he
was arguably attempting to affirm that even if one really did believe the Crown
to be the rightful original possessor of the land in question, there was no way
that said authority could have improved it, cultivated it, or otherwise
increased its value to a greater extent than the colonists. This task instead
fell to the colonists who, in exchange for their labor, gained a superior claim
to the land in question.
One might in fact be inclined to say
that the colonists gained an exclusive claim, but for the myriad complications
then existing within the contemporary Anglo-American legal system vis-à-vis the
use and possession of land. Granting that it was certainly possible – and far
from uncommon – for a given acreage to be sold unconditionally and in its
entirety by one individual to another, this was far from the only means by
which the practical use of land could be transferred between parties. Concepts
like entail and escheat, for example, served to ensure that certain estates
could not be disposed of as their present owners desired and provided for the
automatic Crown appropriation of property in the event of its holder expiring
without a legally valid heir. In both cases, the notion that legal possession
was fundamentally absolute – i.e. that holding the deed to a piece of property
entitled a person to dispose of it as they wished – was called into question.
Entailed estates arguably belonged as much to the original contract holder as
any of their legal heirs in the way that they limited the ability of said
estate to be sold piecemeal rather than as a whole. Escheat, by establishing
the Crown as the default possessor of otherwise unclaimed land, meanwhile
arguably implied that all property falling within the bounds of the British Empire
actually belonged to the monarch of the same. Deeds stating otherwise were thus
in some sense temporary, to be honored only so long as the relevant bloodline
could be maintained.
Then, of course,
there was the matter of rental. Land rental was exceedingly common in British
America, consequent to the widespread use of freehold title. Within most of the
relevant colonies, property was generally purchased on an individual basis from
the appropriate government – said government having commonly acquired is
through negotiation with or conquest of regional indigenous authorities – which
in turn absolved the resulting tenants from all obligations save the annual
payment of so-called “quit-rents.” Whereas these yearly payments historically
functioned as monetary compensation for non-performance of various feudal
obligations – military service chief among them – their remaining purpose by
the end of the 18th century was generally to act as an ongoing
acknowledgment of the property in question’s ultimate owner. As the aforesaid
colonial governments were administered either by an executive appointed by the
Crown or a proprietary owner possessing the sanction of the same, the payment
of quit-rents thus effectively acknowledged that the paramount authority in
matters of property in America was the reigning British monarch. Principles
like entail and escheat arguably also supported this basic assertion by
likewise implying that the average landholder in the Anglo-American world – the
person who lived upon the land in question, worked it, and or otherwise made
productive use of it – remained in a legal sense subordinate to a higher
authority whose interest in or even knowledge of said property was often
exceedingly limited.
Price’s understanding of landed property
– and by extension that of John Locke – tended to be somewhat simpler. Land, he
affirmed in the text of his Observations,
ultimately belonged to the individual(s) whose labor demonstrably increased the
productivity of the same. And while the primacy of this principle did not
preclude a plot or acreage from being transferred between owners absent an
effort of improvement – via a payment of cash, say, or an exchange of goods, or
even as a gift – it did imply that sufficient labor inherently generated
interest. In consequence, regardless of who held the deed on a particular piece
of property, the improvement of it conveyed a right upon the improver to
determine the manner in which it was used. Indeed, taking Locke’s
aforementioned definition of value and ownership at its most fundamental, it
may even have conveyed the superior right. After all, to what extent could an
absentee landlord contribute towards increasing the value of a given plot once
they had assigned that task to a rent-paying tenant? And if it could be proven
that said landlord had in fact contributed nothing at all, why should they then
determine what became of the property in question? While the sheer complexity
of contemporary British property law was not necessarily conducive to these
kinds of questions being posed – nor, indeed, would landlords and leaseholders
been inclined to answer them – they do at least serve to frame Price’s state of
mind as compared to his hypothetical Northite opponent. Fundamentally a
supporter of the status quo, a supporter of the North Ministry would likely
have argued that the fate of all property always fell to the ultimate
deed-holder. Conversely an advocate of individual sovereignty, Price would have
meanwhile affirmed that the fate of a given property was rightly decided by the
person(s) who actually made use of it.
As it concerned the burgeoning
conflict between Great Britain and the Thirteen Colonies, this difference of
opinion on matters of property spoke to the opposing perspectives of Price and
his ideological foes on the aforementioned subject of sovereignty and
authority. Holding that the Crown had been the original owner and granter of
all land subsequently held by the American colonists, and at the same time
maintaining that a transfer of physical ownership did not necessarily involve a
transfer of legal authority, the theoretical supporter of the North Ministry
would naturally be given to conclude that Britain remained the supreme power –
the paramount feudal lord, as it were – over all matters transpiring in the
aforesaid Thirteen Colonies. The amount of time that had passed since the
transfer took place made no difference, nor did the fact that the relevant
colonists had added tremendous value to the property itself. The Crown had
owned the land originally, and in very real sense always would. Price,
conversely maintaining that the colonists had purchased the land fairly and
legally from its original indigenous owners, meanwhile asserted that the labor
exerted by the individuals in question, and the value generated as a result, entitled
them to a greater share of discretion than any authority claiming nominal
ownership over their property. Quit-rents, leases, and escheats
notwithstanding, the land belonged to those who made it useful, “And no power
on earth can have any right to disturb them in the possession of it, or to take
from them without their consent, any part of its produce.”
Having established this basic
ideological dichotomy between his own affirmation of individual sovereignty and
his opponent’s support for a kind of perpetual tenancy, Price next attempted to
juxtapose the implications of the latter against some of the essential
principles of contemporary British citizenship. Granting, for the sake of
argument, the basic premise to which he was opposed – i.e. that Great Britain
had been the original possessor of the land subsequently distributed to the
various American colonies – he asked his readers to then imagine what this logical
construction said about the colonists themselves. Specifically, Price asserted
that the original settlers of the various Anglo-American communities –
Virginia, the Plymouth Colony, Pennsylvania, etc. – would have been unlikely to
migrate from Britain to America had they known that the property they were
thereby acquiring would belong to them in something less than an absolute
sense. Being inculcated with the same understanding of their sovereign rights
as those of their countrymen who chose to remain behind in Britain, these
pioneering settlers would surely not have agreed to take part in such a
hazardous venture where they not convinced that the liberties to which they
were entitled as subjects of the Crown were guaranteed to the same extent in
America as they had been in the land of their birth. That the colonial charters
these same people labored under appeared to support exactly this expectation –
documents, “Which promised them the enjoyment of all the rights of Englishmen; and allowed them to tax
themselves, and to be governed by legislatures of their own” – appears very
strongly to validate this claim.
And even if this
weren’t the case, Price further avowed that the basic dictates of reason argued
powerfully against the scenario that his hypothetical opponent seemed to be
proposing. As he described their position, certain contemporary supporters of
the North Ministry evidently believed that the original settlers of British
America, by the act of migration, had tacitly agreed that the government they
were ostensibly leaving behind – over which they would no longer possess even
the barest measure of control – could and should continue to exercise final
authority over the disposition of their property and the fulfilment of their
rights. This particular understanding was undeniably a convenient one as suited
the priorities of the North Ministry, fundamentally absolving them of any need
to respect the claimed rights of the inhabitants of the Thirteen Colonies. To
Price’s thinking, of course, it was also almost wholly illogical. “It is
inconsistent with common sense to imagine,” he wrote accordingly, “That any
people would ever think of settling in a distant country, on any such
condition, as that the people from whom they withdrew, should forever be
masters of their property, and have power to subject them to any modes of
government they pleased.” Had terms to this effect been made plain to the
relevant individuals at the time of their departure from Great Britain, it
followed, the sense of their sovereign rights possessed by each of them would
surely have prevent their departure, or else ensured that more reasonable
stipulations were agreed to. To affirm that Britain was the original
distributor of property in America, and that it retained final authority over
the disposition of the same, was thereby also essentially to argue that the
first settlers of said territory gave up their rights – knowingly or
unknowingly – upon their departure in such a way as to make them impossible for
their descendants to ever recover.
Doubtless Price’s
intention was for his readers to interpret this scenario as being fundamentally
preposterous. Not only was it essentially unthinkable within the context of
Britain’s libertarian, rights-conscious political culture that any individual
or group would agree to forfeit the exercise of their rights and those of their
progeny in exchange for land and isolation, but it would surely have beggared
belief for the average Briton to realize that their liberties could so easily
be abrogated by way of physical distance and the possession of property. Certainly,
it would be difficult to imagine any contemporary British observers of the
ongoing Anglo-American crisis agreeing to make such a bargain themselves.
Decades of cultural self-assurance, the mythologizing of the Glorious
Revolution (1688) and the Bill of Rights (1689), and the consequent ideological
sanctification of the British Constitution would have offered tremendous
barriers to the same. Likewise – laying aside for a moment the functional
novelty that the Thirteen Colonies represented – it would take a concerted
effort of will to conceive of very many constituents of the contemporary
British government who would have granted that Parliament and the Crown could ignore
the fundamental rights of certain of their subjects depending on where they
lived or from whom they acquired what landed property they possessed.
Mainstream British constitutional theory simply couldn’t account for that kind
of discretionary power. Even residents of under-represented boroughs –
burgeoning industrial centers like Manchester, Leeds, and Glasgow, for example
– at least enjoyed the recognition of their property and the security of their
basic civil rights. The inhabitants of British America were evidently to be
denied even these seemingly meagre guarantees, and for no more convincing
reason than that it suited the ministry of Lord North to do so.
Price quite naturally
refused to countenance the kind of senseless, slipshod reasoning that would
have to be deployed in order to support such a position. The founding settlers
of the Thirteen Colonies, being proud, rights-conscious Britons, would no more
have agreed to curtail their own liberties by migrating than would any of their
18th century counterparts. Nor would they have agreed to such an
exchange if it had been clearly presented to them. It therefore only made sense
to conclude that they had not done so, that their rights were in the same state
upon arriving in America as they had been on departing from Britain, and that
their descendants had inherited said rights undiminished and fully extant.
Logic would accept nothing less. Neither would any right-thinking British
person. Ever fond of granting a premise only to then tear it down, of course,
Price carried this assertion yet further by arguing that even consent could not
have altered the state of American liberties. Even if the pioneering settlers
of the Thirteen Colonies had known what it was there were supposedly in for –
if, for example, the limits to be placed on their rights were spelled out
explicitly in their respective governing charters – he nevertheless avowed,
“They would, in my opinion, be no more bound by them, than if it had been
stipulated with them, that they should go naked, or expose themselves to the
incursion of wolves and tigers.” Though this obviously represents a somewhat
fanciful construction, the intention behind it was most certainly an earnest
one. To Price’s thinking, being deprived of one’s sovereign rights –
unknowingly or by mutual agreement – was tantamount to being exposed to
potentially life-ending peril. No government had the power to compel its
subjects to make such an agreement, or the right to hold them to one that was
freely offered. Government – in the Lockean sense – being of essence the result
of a consensual bargain whereby the lives of those involved were made more
secure, stable, and safe, no institution so conceived could ever rightfully
support policies that contributed to a loss of these same guarantees. The North
Ministry, in this regard, was no exception, the claims of its supporters
notwithstanding.
No comments:
Post a Comment