Among
the most troubling accusations leveled at John Jay upon the receipt of his
namesake treaty in the United States – from a modern perspective, if not that
of the late 18th century – concerned his evident unwillingness to
hold Great Britain to account for the former American slaves it had carried off
at the conclusion of the Revolutionary War. Thousands of these formerly subjugated
persons had been transported out of the nascent American republic during the
British evacuations in 1783 – having either been liberated during various
British campaigns or enlisted in British military service – in evident
violation of Article 7 of the Treaty of Paris. And as the perceived offense seemed
to attack both the roots of plantation agriculture and the notion of private
property, it was both particularly galling to southern Republicans and formed a
large part of what they expected any treaty with Great Britain to address. That
Jay’s treaty had entirely failed to attend to this issue consequently shaped
much of the resulting Republican criticism. The agreement was an instrument of
faction, Alexander Dallas had accordingly declared, because it prejudiced
expanding trade – the favored industry of the North, where the Federalists were
strongest – over the satisfaction of injuries done to American planters – the
economic elites of the South, where the Republicans largely held sway. If Jay,
it thus followed, had truly been intent
on serving the interests of the whole of his nation, he would have sought
compensation from Britain for the seized slaves as zealously as he had appeared
to pursue access to British ports in the East and West Indies.
To
this manner of critique, Hamilton offered a characteristically verbose response
in No. III of The Defence that was
both exhaustively thorough and broadly assumptive. The core of the issue at
hand, he first proposed, were in fact the mutually exclusive interpretations of
the aforementioned seventh article of the Treaty of Paris supported by Great
Britain and the United States, respectively. “His Britannic Majesty shall [,]”
Hamilton accordingly quoted from the aforementioned peace agreement, “with all
convenient speed and without causing any destruction or carrying
away any negroes or other property of
the American Inhabitants withdraw all his armies garrisons and fleets
from the U States.” Whereas the United States of America contended that this
passage was meant to convey, “That no negroes or other articles which had been American property should be
carried away,” Great Britain held that its intention was to ensure, “That no
new destruction was to be committed and that negroes or other articles which at
the time of the cessation of hostilities continued to be the property of the American inhabitants […]
should be foreborne to [be] carried away.” The key difference, it seemed, lay
in the significance of the word “property” and in the manner that it applied to
the formerly enslaved persons at the time of their evacuation from the United
States. They were either still the chattel of American planters or they were
free persons; thus, either Article 7 applied to them specifically or it was
meant to refer to those still in a state of enslavement at the time of the
British evacuation.
The
latter construction – that supported by Great Britain – was by Hamilton’s
reckoning the correct one. The reasons for this were hardly simple, though his
characterizations of the same seemed to treat them as though they were. First,
he argued, the laws of war – in the late 18th century little more
than a loose code of behavior – awards to an enemy, “The use and enjoyment […] of
all real property […] and the
absolute ownership of all personal
property which falls into his hands.” The distinction between these two species
of property was on the level of moveable and immovable – i.e. land and any
associated buildings and improvements versus personal items like furniture,
documents, art objects, livestock, or tools. Second, he affirmed that the laws
of the American states in which slavery was legal – in 1795, ten of sixteen –
treated enslaved persons as personal property, “Like horses, cattle and other
moveables [.]” In consequence, upon their coming into possession of an enemy
during wartime – in this case the British Army during the Revolutionary War –
they became the property of that enemy on the same terms as had any other
personal effects. It thereafter became the indisputable right of the relevant
British military authorities to dispose of their newfound property as they saw
fit, by transporting said slaves to another part of the British Empire, or by
setting them free, or both, or neither. And in the event that liberty was
granted, that grant was irrevocable, as “Nothing in the laws of Nations or in
those of Great Britain will authorise the resumption of liberty once granted to
a human being [.]”
Third, while admitting that the British policy of offering
to American slaves their freedom in exchange for a period of enlistment in the
British Army was perhaps “an illiberal species of warfare [,]” Hamilton
asserted that said policy nevertheless did
not represent a violation of the rules of war as they were then understood. In
consequence, it could likewise not be claimed by disgruntled American
plantation owners that the arguably dishonorable quality of the practice itself
in any way altered the fact that their property – i.e. their slaves – had
indeed changed hands. Fourth, because the article in question makes explicit
reference to “negroes or other property,” it stood to reason that
slaves were to be effected in the same manner by the terms therein as any other
piece of chattel. And in turn the attribution of said property to “the American
inhabitants” suggested to Hamilton that, “Whatever had lost that character
could not be the object of the stipulation [.]” Bearing these two assertions in
mind, then, it seemed to him inconceivable that any American should claim the
return of a slave – or an equivalent compensation – without also laying the
same requirement upon every other piece of personal property that the British
Army had seized and taken away. Nevertheless, this was precisely what any
number of aggrieved former slave owners had effected to do. While clamoring to
be reimbursed for their captured slaves – which they universally regarded as
personal property – they made no such demands of whatever horses, or oxen, or
other personal effects that had been likewise carried off. “And yet,” Hamilton avowed,
“The demand for a horse or an ox or a piece of furniture would have been as
completely within the terms “negroes and other property” as a negro.” By
accepting the transfer of ownership of their less valuable personal goods,
therefore, former slave owners had tacitly endorsed the loss of their human
property as well.
The
fifth point Hamilton offered in favor of the above-cited British interpretation
of Article 7 of the Treaty of Paris shifted the debate from the legal status of
the relevant American slaves to the moral implications of their eventual fate. “In
the interpretation of Treaties,” he first explained,
“things odious or immoral are not to be presumed.” And as
causing, “Negroes, who had been induced to quit their Masters on the faith of
Official proclamations promising them liberty, to fall again under the yoke of
their masters and into slavery is as odious and immoral a
thing as can be conceived,” it would not have become any subsequent party to
assume that such was the intention of the authors of the Treaty of Paris. Not
only would pursuing such a course of action have run counter to what Hamilton
described – in a fit of righteousness likely not shared by some of his Southern
critics – as, “The general interests of humanity [,]” but it would have
imposed, “An act of perfidy on one of the contracting parties [.]” The latter
was doubtless understood as a matter of particular sensitivity, though it may
not seem so to a modern observer. During the course of the Revolutionary War,
Great Britain had indeed promised freedom and protection – through proclamations
issued by the likes of Virginia’s Royal Governor Lord Dunmore (1730-1809) and
General Sir Henry Clinton (1730-1795) – to all slaves then held in bondage in
the rebellious American colonies. Bearing this promise in mind, and the
reigning 18th century preoccupation with honor and integrity in
public affairs, it evidently struck Hamilton as fairly unlikely that the
British negotiators of the Treaty of Paris would have willingly invalidated
such a clearly stated obligation. And if indeed it had not been the intention
of Great Britain to revoke its pledge to the American slaves taken under its
care during the Revolutionary War, then there was no basis for anyone in the
United States to read Article 7 as having done so.
The
sixth – and thankfully last – reason put forward by Hamilton in No. III of The Defence for the validity of the
British position as to the former slaves they had taken under their protection
was perhaps the most subtle and the most difficult to follow. This was
particularly the case because Hamilton chose to frame it less as a positive
explanation than a series of refutations and counterproposals. The specific
object of contention was the aforementioned provision embedded within the
seventh article of the Treaty of Paris – i.e. that the British would evacuate “without
causing any destruction, or carrying away any Negroes or other property of the
American inhabitants [.]” Whereas Hamilton appeared to understand the two
clauses therein as being linked – that no new destruction would be committed by
the evacuating British personnel, including the further seizure of personal
property like slaves – he attributed to certain critics of the Jay Treaty a
desire to separate the two and characterize the former as superfluous. Because,
“the stipulation to surrender implied of itself that it was to be done without
depredation [,]” they were to have claimed, there would have been no need for
the authors of the Treaty of Paris to anticipate further violence. In
consequence, as the first clause was essentially meaningless, the second would
be presumed to refer to all slaves taken into British custody rather than those
seized solely during the aforesaid evacuation.
This
hypothetical reading of the seventh article of the Treaty of Paris, Hamilton
avowed, was fundamentally incorrect. The fact that British and American
negotiators had inserted a clause intended to prevent further depredations
clearly indicated that they nurtured some specific fear that further destruction
was likely to be wrought upon American property during the evacuation of
British military personnel. The clause “without causing any destruction” was
therefore purposeful rather than superfluous. And as, “It must have such a
sense in one part authorises the conclusion that the remainder of the
clause has a similar sense [,]” the following clause, “or carrying away any
Negroes or other property of the American inhabitants [,]” must therefore have
drawn its significance from the former. Granted, the significance of this
conclusion – and its phrasing in particular – is far from obvious. Judging from
the context in which it was proposed, what Hamilton appeared keen to
communicate was the connection he perceived between of the destruction that the
British had promised to forego upon their evacuation and their pledge to avoid
carrying away any of the slaves they had seized. Inferring that the former was
included in the final text of the Treaty of Paris for the specific purpose of
protecting the further seizure of American property, he thereafter concluded
that the latter was intended as an attendant consequence. The British, he
essentially believed, had promised not to do any more harm on their way out the
door, including taking custody of any further slaves. This necessarily ran
counter to the contention of certain critics of the Jay Treaty – i.e. that
British military authorities would refrain from causing further destruction
during the course of their departure and would
endeavor to return the slaves they had seized over the course of the war – and
in fact invalidated it.
The reason that Hamilton offered
these varied and various justifications – beyond the certain pleasure he took
in holding forth on a given topic – was as he had stated above, “To ascertain
by a preliminary discussion, the impossibility of bringing the other party to
concede the point.” In this case, the point was the apparent unwillingness of
American envoy John Jay to insist upon either the return of former slaves
seized during the late Revolutionary War or seek appropriate compensation for
the same. Jay had not approached the topic, Hamilton effected to argue, for these reasons, the combined result of
which was presumably to convince him that the matter was not worth pursuing.
Whether or not this was a convincing mode of argument is something of an open
question, but one that need not be entertained. Of consequence to the present
discussion are rather the ideological implications of Hamilton’s method. Tasked
– by his own appointment – with defending what he and his fellow Federalists
considered to be one of the premiere policy achievements of the contemporary
United States government, the kinds of arguments he saw fit to deploy were
almost certainly of a piece with the principles and perspective of that
selfsame political faction. Bearing this in mind, the characteristic that would
most immediately suggest itself as indicative of a particularly Federalist
mindset from among the six cited validations is the evident willingness with
which Hamilton freely and broadly interpreted the meaning and significance of
certain phrases, concepts, and principles.
Recall, to that end, the
first and second arguments Hamilton offered in favor of Britain’s
interpretation of the relevant provision of the Treaty of Paris. On one hand he
claimed that the laws of war permitted an enemy to make use of whatever real
property came into his possession and claim ownership of whatever moveable
property he could seize. And on the other he asserted that the laws of the
various slave-holding states qualified enslaved persons as personal property,
therefore rendering them as vulnerable as any horse, hatchet, or handcart to such
wartime confiscations. The end result: American slaves were not stolen by the
British occupiers of the United States, but rather passed to their ownership as
would any other piece of personal property during a time of war. As presented
by Hamilton it was a convincing argument, though also a rather presumptuous
one.
The laws of war, for
instance, were far from a well-defined codex. As of 1795 – and indeed until at
least the middle of the 19th century – there were no written treaties
or pacts establishing the standards and conventions of warfare between European
states. Conduct in war was instead defined by tradition, precedent, and
culture, entirely unaccompanied by any mechanism of oversight or enforcement. Granted,
certain landmark diplomatic agreements – like the Peace of Westphalia, which
ended the Thirty Years’ War (1618-1648) – had gone some way towards
establishing notions of political sovereignty and religious obligation. But
warfare itself essentially remained the province of gentlemen-soldiers whose
turn of mind tended to be more honor-bound than legalistic. In consequence,
while customs as to the treatment of prisoners, or the status of private
property, or the rules of parlay were widely recognized among European
combatants at the time Hamilton penned The
Defence, they were almost entirely unwritten, and so their application in a
given context could not be formally checked, confirmed, or invalidated. His
invocation of the established norms of property use and possession during armed
conflict accordingly constituted a species of logic that was both communally sanctioned
and exceedingly flexible. His principle audience would doubtless have
recognized the customs he invoked, understood them as possessing a foundation
in the long history of Western warfare, and accorded them some degree of
credence as a result. And yet, if they happened to disagree with Hamilton’s
particular characterization, there existed no higher authority or primary text
to which they could refer. He had quoted a custom rather than a law, and could
not easily be held to account for misinterpreting what was not written.
Where this notion – that the
unwritten laws of war were as weighty was they were malleable – becomes
particularly interesting is in the way Hamilton proceeded to apply the received
understanding of property and warfare to the codified laws of the certain
American states. As he scrupulously pointed out, the statutes then in force in
the slave-holding jurisdictions of the United States gave enslaved persons the
legal status of private property. In consequence, all other laws or constitutional
provisions which applied to private property applied equally to slaves within
the confines of the relevant states. For example, the article of the North
Carolina Declaration of Rights which stated, “That in all controversies
at law, respecting property, the ancient mode of trial, by jury […] ought to
remain sacred and inviolable” interacted with the cited laws to ensure that
trials concerning the ownership of slaves would be conducted in the presence of
a jury. To this same effect, Hamilton asserted that the cited laws of war
affecting the seizure and use of private property by an enemy combatant
likewise also encompassed slaves. While this was an eminently logical
deduction, it also almost certainly fell outside the intentions of the relevant
state legislatures. In codifying the legal status of enslaved persons,
lawmakers in Virginia, and Georgia, and indeed North Carolina were doubtless
aiming to preserve, promote, streamline, or clarify an institution that formed
the very foundation of their economic well-being. The laws of war and their
application to enslaved peoples was likely very far from their minds, and they
surely did not mean to provide a legal opportunity for the private property of
hundreds of slave owners to be seized and transported out of the United States.
And yet, as stated above, Hamilton’s reasoning was outwardly
sound. By the standards and customs of the late 18th century,
private property could indeed be appropriated by enemy combatants during war.
And by the laws of the slave-holding states within the contemporary American
republic, enslaved persons were considered private property. It hardly
constituted a logical leap, therefore, for Hamilton – or Jay, or the relevant
British authorities – to claim that all those American slaves that had been
transported out of the United States during the British military evacuation had
ceased to be the property of their former American owners at the time that they
entered into British custody. That no one had previously intended this as a
possible reading of state property laws or military customs made no difference.
What mattered is that it was possible to interpret the appropriate sources that
way, and that the resulting interpretation enjoyed the support of a body or
institution powerful enough or influential enough to enforce it.
No comments:
Post a Comment