Considerations on the Nature and Extent of
the Legislative Authority of the British Parliament, Part V: Reason, Liberty,
and Law, contd.
Lest if appear, based on the
contents of the previous week’s entry in this series, that James Wilson was
motivated to offer a critique of late 18th century British tax
policy solely by a rigid personal adherence to reason and logic, it now bears
examining the depth of his dedication to the principles he and his fellow
colonists held most dear. Liberty – the second ingredient in the Wilson
cocktail – formed an essential part of the central argument in Considerations. As eager as he might
have been to pick apart the various illogical aspects of the British position, Wilson
never seemed to lose sight of what he and his fellow colonists knew was at
stake – namely, the fundamental rights upon which their legal and political
culture was based. British liberties, as he called them, were evidently as dear
to his American cohorts as their very lives. Their governments – in
Massachusetts, the Carolinas, Pennsylvania, or New York – were built upon the
model embodied by Parliament and intended in the main to protect these
liberties while serving the community at large. Trial by jury, the writ of
habeas corpus, the right to bear arms, and to be taxed only by representatives
elected for that purpose; colonial Americans considered these guarantees to be
a part of their birthright. To lose them or see them violated was to give up a
part of themselves; a part of what they felt made their civilization – British
civilization – perfect.
By attempting to tax those who
had no part in electing its members – through the passage of the Stamp Act
(1765) and the Townshend Duties (1767) – Parliament had committed this very
crime, knowingly or unknowingly, and effectively called into question the true
nature of the Anglo-American relationship. Political implications aside – which
were many – they had struck at the heart of something core to the cultural
identity of British Americans. Wilson perceived this with characteristic
insight, claiming in the third paragraph of Considerations
that the virulent reaction the offending acts of Parliament received in America
were rooted in, “A regard for that nation, from whom we have sprung, and from
whom we boast to have derived the spirit which prompts us to oppose their
unfriendly measures [.]” Colonial Americans, though in truth descended from
French, Dutch, and German stock as well as English, Scottish, and Irish,
strongly identified with British culture and history. The Magna Carta (1215)
and the Glorious Revolution (1688) loomed large in their collective
understanding of acceptable legal and political norms, and an affection for
Parliament as a model of responsible administration conditioned the way they
perceived their respective local legislatures. While it is true, based on
firsthand accounts, that certain 18th century colonists lucky enough
to travel to Britain proper were struck by their own comparative provincialism
and began to self-identify as “American,” British law and British culture was
still in many ways the wellspring of American identity as late as the
1770s.
With this in mind, Wilson’s
assertion that his fellow colonists were too proud of their British cultural
inheritance to allow even the British government to threaten it isn’t all that
surprising. As discussed in weeks past, he identified the core of his
adopted-countrymen’s opposition to 1760s British tax policy as an attachment
to, “The principles of justice and freedom, and of the British constitution.”
For many people in Britain and in America, these concepts were at the centre of
who they thought they were as a people. Beyond the folk songs, and the Morris
Dancing, and stories about saints and dragons, 18th century English/British
identity was really rooted in the dense, often confusing, and not-infrequently
bloody political history of “splendid Albion.” Legal concepts like habeas
corpus – the “Great Writ” first recorded during the reign of Henry II
(1133-1189) – and trial by jury – a fusion of Norse, Saxon, and Norman
practices – carried the inexorable weight of tradition. British liberties had
been fought for over centuries, in civil wars and rebellions between kings, and
barons, and common people, and the resulting sense of legacy exerted a powerful
effect on the way politically-active Britons (wherever they were in the world)
perceived themselves. To be British was to be a part of something ancient and
immeasurably important, to know one’s rights and actively utilize them.
Considerations communicates this sense of pride – in the liberties inherent
to British citizenship and the people who helped establish and protect them –
in a rather poetic, though no less effective, fashion. “Such is the admirable
temperament of the British constitution!” Wilson declared in paragraph
thirty-three.
Such
glorious fabrick of Britain’s liberty – the pride of her citizens – the envy of
her neighbours – planned by her legislators – erected by her patriots –
maintained entire by numerous generations past! may it be maintained entire by
numerous generations to come!
Though he was of British birth and
education, Wilson wrote these words as an American and for an American
audience. Unless he was particularly tone-deaf, it thus seems sensible to
conclude that many of his fellow colonists shared his enthusiastic regard for
Great Britain’s political and legal culture. Indeed, it is noteworthy when one
considers how heavily influenced later phases of the American Revolution would
be by the abstract, natural rights philosophy of the Enlightenment – thanks in
no small part to the efforts of men like Thomas Jefferson and James Madison –
that Considerations is almost
entirely preoccupied with preserving a distinctly British socio-political
ideal. Rather than appeal to a moral principle that had no overt cultural
association – Jefferson’s self-evident truths, for example, or his allusion in
the Declaration of Independence to “Nature” and Nature’s God” – Wilson identified
himself, and indeed the entire opposition to the Stamp Act and Townshend Duties,
as the proud heirs of “generations past” whose sacrifices in the name of
British liberty were eminently worthy of veneration.
The thirty-fourth paragraph of Considerations also bears this sentiment
out. Continuing on from his passionate declaration of pride in British legal
and political customs, Wilson asked his readers, “Can the Americans, who are
descended from British ancestors, and inherit all their rights, be blamed – can
they be blamed by their brethren in Britain – for claiming still to enjoy those
rights?” Through this rhetorical inquiry Wilson appeared to voice a degree of
disbelief, presumably aimed at any in Britain who expressed surprise or
incredulity at the vehement reaction of the American colonists to being taxed
without representation in Parliament. How was it that the elected
representatives of the British people had forgotten that the American colonists
were British, too? How could they fail
to see that their attempts to tax the people of British America violated the
rights and liberties that they themselves cherished? In the mind of James
Wilson, it seemed that there was no inherent difference between British people
who lived in Britain and British people who lived in America – they all valued
their rights, derived them from the same source, and based their shared
cultural identity upon them. Certainly, being from Yorkshire was not quite like
being from Bristol, which was in turn not entirely like being from
Massachusetts, or Georgia, or New York. But the paltry differences in accent and
local custom between these regional identities surely paled in comparison to
the core cultural legacy they all shared.
Though perhaps not spoken quite
so explicitly, the significance of his American countrymen’s abiding
Britishness permeated much of the case Wilson put forth in Considerations. “No taxation without representation,” the famous
cry in opposition to the Stamp Act that has since become a cultural touchstone
in American political discourse, was itself based on well-established (as of
the 1760s) British parliamentary practice. Much is made by Wilson in his
pamphlet of the importance of this principle to Britain’s historical and
cultural identity. Taxation by consent was one of the demands obtained from
John I (1166-1216) when he was made to sign the Magna Carta in 1215, attempts
by Charles I (1600-1649) to tax his subjects outside the authority of
Parliament were one of the core causes of the English Civil War, and the Bill
of Rights (1689) accused James II (1633-1701) of unjustly extracting money from
the people via the prerogatives of the Crown. Considerations touched on all of these historical examples, and
went into significant detail as to the importance contemporary Britons placed
upon paying taxes only in exchange for representation in the House of Commons.
From Wilson’s perspective, it seemed, “no taxation without representation” was
not a novel challenge to the status quo, but rather the reassertion of a
long-established custom. Time and tide would come to alter the tenor of the
discussion that Considerations put
forward – British intransigence would in short order sour the colonists on the
prospect of reconciliation – but in 1768 it was still possible to hope the
native soil which first nurtured the rights that 18th century
Americans cherished had not been completely poisoned against their continued
growth.
The final ingredient in the
Wilson cocktail – law – requires perhaps the least elaboration then the
previous two. A prior entry in this series has hopefully already made clear
that Considerations nearly groans
under the weight of the precedents Wilson saw fit to cite. A lawyer by trade,
and a scholar by inclination, it should come as no surprise that his interest
in statue and case law and his talent as a litigator shaped the kinds of
arguments he chose to make in defence of his American countrymen’s threatened
liberties. That being said, by way of a conclusion, a few more words on the
subject would seem appropriate.
Because there is more to Wilson’s
evident attachment to the common law practice of citing precedent than might
appear at first blush. Yes, he clearly nurtured a high regard for the laws and
customs of the country of his birth. And yes, his inclination and ability to
argue in favor of preserving the political and legal status quo of late 18th
century British America speaks to how widespread such conservative sentiments
likely were. But on a more personal level, James Wilson’s tendency to seek out
past examples as a guide to present action, and his faith in structure, law,
and consensus, speak volumes about his character. And they also speak volumes
about how we in the 21st century should endeavor to understand the
Founding Generation and their legacy. Though Wilson is not, and indeed has never
been, the most well-known among his cohorts – that prize usually falling to
George Washington, Thomas Jefferson, or more recently to that perennial upstart
Alexander Hamilton – his particular brand of legalistic conservatism is no less
representative of the ideology of the American Founding than Jefferson’s
radicalism, Washington’s affection for classical republican ideals, or
Hamilton’s penchant for realpolitik. Granted, his attachment to British
liberties, British law, and British customs might conceivably appear rather
limp and reactionary against the radical break with tradition that the Revolution
ultimately became, but even in a narrative full of war heroes,
gentleman-philosophers, and charismatic diplomats, a conservative Scottish
country lawyer still had an important role to play.
Though
his face adorns no mountainside, James Wilson unequivocally shaped what the
United States of America is today. As a member of the Philadelphia Convention
of 1787, his deep knowledge of government, politics, history, and law
made him one of the most prominent contributors to the discussions therein. He
spoke, it has been recorded, over one hundred sixty times during the assembly’s
proceedings – second only to fellow political scholar James Madison –
recommended the three-fifths compromise as a solution to lingering
disagreements between the northern and southern states over the apportionment
of taxes and Congressional representatives, and helped produce the first
complete draft of the Constitution as a member of the five-member Committee of
Detail. Though they may be impossible to quantify exactly, his contributions to
the form and character of the United States Constitution – still in force and
substantially unchanged two hundred twenty-seven years later – were accordingly far from
insubstantial. His subsequent service on the Supreme Court as an Associate
Justice between 1789 and 1798 further extended his influence on the nation’s
public life. Granted, the Court only heard nine cases during his tenure, but
the significance of his presence should not be dismissed. Every disagreement
that came before the assembled justices had the potential to draw upon his
understanding of law, and precedent, and history. And so, every decision they
handed down in part belonged to him. Though not a legislator, he nonetheless
helped make law in America by lending his expertise to the highest judicial
body in the land. Consequently, Wilson’s attention to detail, and his regard
for precedent, logic, and principle, is incredibly significant to understanding
how and why America looks the way it does.
Because, I hope it has become
clear by now, the American Revolution was a collaborative effort. Thirteen
colonies, and from each of them dozens if not hundreds of soldiers, merchants,
statesmen, farmers, and artisans, banded together in the common pursuit of the
freedom to enjoy the liberties they understood to be theirs by right of birth.
Some, it must be said, exerted a greater influence on the end result than
others. Or at least, some of them have enjoyed more colorful legacies than
others. This is the nature of things, it seems. Jefferson and Washington and
Hamilton have come to define what we think about the Revolution and its meaning
in no small part because their personalities and their accomplishments fit very
easily into a pleasing, straightforward, self-affirming narrative. James
Wilson, with his steel-trap mind and highly structure rhetorical style, is
conversely a little harder to locate within the accepted story of the American
Founding. He was British-born and
British-educated, cautious, highly pragmatic, and well-versed in the law. And,
like fellow Pennsylvanian John Dickinson, he was a moderate. He came to support
the cause of independence gradually, and by inclination would seem to have
preferred reconciliation with Britain. Characterized thusly, it would be all
too easy to think of Wilson as some sort of reluctant revolutionary – someone
out of step with the radical mainstream who had to be coerced into accepting
what many of his colleagues believed was inevitable.
This, it must be made exceedingly
clear, was not the case. In 1768, the year Considerations
was written and the year British troops were dispatched to occupy Boston in
light of continued resistance to the Townshend Duties, Wilson’s position was
the mainstream. American independence remained an open question well into 1774
and 1775, and gained traction only after peaceful measures aimed at reconciling
Britain and the colonies had been rebuffed by the former. Up to that fateful
turning point, the conversation taking place in state legislatures and
inter-colonial assemblies was as Wilson described in the first paragraph of Considerations: “Does the legislative
authority of the British parliament extend over [America?]” The text of said
pamphlet attempted exhaustively to answer that question, and in so doing
exposed the true contours of the controversy at hand. In that sense, and
because it was evidently very well-regarded at the time of its publication, Considerations can be looked upon by
students of America’s Founding as a kind of guide to the true nature of the
crises that precipitated the Revolution. It really wasn’t, as it so often
stated, about taxes, and it wasn’t, though it might be comforting to think so,
about the repudiation of monarchism. Rather, as Wilson capably and
painstakingly explained, the late 18th century dispute between
Britain and the American colonies began as a disagreement about the nature of
empire, citizenship, and rights.
Give it a read.
No comments:
Post a Comment