Having discussed the conservatism
of James Wilson’s Considerations, and
its abundant use of English/British political, historical, and legal
precedents, it remains to unpack certain additional elements of Wilson’s
rhetorical style before we part ways in our customary fashion. Specifically,
I’d like to take a look at what I’ve taken to referring to as the “James Wilson
Cocktail.” There are, in my estimation, three points of focus that seemed to
guide Wilson’s overall approach in Considerations.
Each are touched upon with a similar degree of consideration, and together they
combine to quite effectively drive home the pamphlet’s central conceit. They
are, as the title of this post suggests, reason, liberty, and law. Wilson’s
perspective on the nature of the Anglo-American relationship seemed to be
defined by each in turn, and the questions he periodically asked of his
hypothetical critics seemed mainly intent on one or all of these basic
concerns. Reason: does the alteration of the connection between Britain and
American the colonies embodied by the Stamp Act and the Townshend Duties serve
a useful purpose? Liberty: is said alteration harmful or beneficial to the
fundamental rights possessed by every Englishman? Law: is the selfsame
alteration grounded in established law and practice, or is it an unjustified
innovation? If the supporters of late 18th century British tax
policy had managed to satisfy all of these inquiries, no doubt they would have
satisfied Wilson. Considerations,
however, makes it clear that they did not, and in explaining why, the pamphlet
provides tremendous insight into the thought process of one of America’s most
intellectually rigorous Founders.
Let us begin with reason, as all
good policy arguably must. Throughout Considerations,
Wilson asserted that utility was the most basic, and often the most important,
rationale by which a measure, or a structure, or an institution ought to be
judged. The very existence of government itself, he argued accordingly in
paragraph eight, was owed to this manner of evaluation. “All lawful government
is founded on the consent of those who are subject to it,” he claimed, and,
“Such consent was given with a view to ensure and to increase the happiness of
the governed, above what they could enjoy in an independent and unconnected
state of nature.” In effect, having required a surrender of independence, any
legitimate government must offer a gift of safety and stability in return,
beyond what any single person could provide on their own. In light of the
ubiquity of this fundamental social transaction, Wilson evidently believed it
to be a basic maxim that, “The happiness of the society is the first law of
every government.” From this statement it follows that the author of Considerations understood the ends of
government to be of greater importance than the means at their disposal. Laws,
and customs, and institutions, and power structures were all well and good, but
unless they served the needs of the general population, they were fundamentally
without purpose.
In relation to the subject of his
1768 pamphlet – the validity of Parliament’s attempts to directly tax the
citizens of British America – Wilson’s utilitarian understanding of government
gave rise to a series of fairly simple questions. “Will it ensure and increase
the happiness of the American colonies,” he asked in paragraph ten of Considerations,
That the
parliament of Great Britain should possess a supreme, irresistible,
uncontrolled authority over them? Is such an authority consistent with their
liberty? Have they any security that it will be employed only for their good?
Above any discussions of the
authority Parliament possessed or the precedents that validated it, Wilson
seemed keen that his fellow colonists ask themselves whether bending to the
declared will of the British government would make their lives better or worse.
If they determined that the latter was true, it begged the further question:
what purpose did continuing to recognize British authority serve? As Wilson
elaborated further in paragraph sixty of Considerations,
America was not a conquered nation. The citizens of Virginia, Pennsylvania, or
Massachusetts recognized the authority of the British Crown because they chose
to, rather than because it had been forced upon them as a consequence of
invasion. This being the case, it followed that they should expect something in
exchange for their loyalty. The Anglo-American relationship, as Wilson
characterized it, was in large part a transaction – access to natural resources
and consumer markets in exchange for protection and consumer goods, more or
less. If this unspoken contract ceased to be advantageous for its American
participants – if the Stamp Act was indicative of Britain’s priorities going
forward – it would seem only logical for the colonists to sue for a return to
the status quo or seek a fundamental renegotiation.
In
fairness to its author, Considerations
did not suggest that independence was a viable solution to the Anglo-American
crisis, or endorse any variation thereof. Rather, Wilson seemed intent on
probing the British position, holding its various arguments to a rigorous
standard of inquiry, and encouraging his fellow colonists to do the same.
Parliament, he argued throughout the bulk of paragraphs eighteen to thirty, made
sense. It was well balanced and well structured, elections to the House of
Commons were protected by a multitude of statutes and customs, the powers of
the House of Lords was checked, the prerogatives of the Crown were sensible,
and the whole of it was grounded upon an abiding respect for the foundational
rights enjoyed by all British subjects. It served a purpose, he asserted, and
served it well. Allowing Parliament to extend its authority over the
unrepresented colonists of British America, however, in violation of most of
the laws that governed its operation and the essential principles of the
British Constitution could serve no purpose that wasn’t directly harmful to the
interests of the colonies. The conclusion, for the people of British America,
was thus a fairly simple one; allowing Britain to levy direct taxes in America,
as they had attempted with the Stamp Act and the Townshend Duties, was
manifestly impractical. What this meant going forward, beyond endorsing a
return to the status quo, Wilson seemed disinclined to speculate.
In
spite of his seeming lack of interest in contemplating a future for the
American colonies absent British supervision – a position that was, it bears
repeating, very common among Americans in the early 1770s – Wilson’s tendency
to probe his chosen subject of inquiry with rigorous logic seemed to
nonetheless reveal a latent flaw inherent in the prospect of maintaining the
Anglo-American relationship. As he maintained throughout Considerations, a large part of what Wilson felt rendered
Parliament’s efforts to extend its taxing authority into American climes
invalid was the fact that every citizen of British America possessed the same
right to be taxed only by their elected representatives as the people of
Britain proper. While the ancestors of the late 18th century
colonial population – and in some cases immigrant colonists themselves – had
given up the prospect of being any longer represented in Parliament, they had
not relinquished the associated rights. They were, they maintained, British
subjects, and happily so. But only the colonial legislatures that they
themselves elected could collect from them the direct taxes that Parliament
claimed in Britain. Wilson wholeheartedly endorsed this position, but also
asked a number of questions that seemed to call into doubt the logic behind
this particular characterization of British citizenship.
Really,
though, citizenship is the wrong word. In a 21st century context, it
carries any number of complex connotations; passports, border checks,
extradition treaties, and swearing-in ceremonies. In the 18th
century, being a British citizen was a somewhat more informal and fluid
prospect. A native-born person living in Britain after, say, 1700 could
certainly be assured of certain legal protections based on their being a
subject of the monarchy. They were entitled to representation in Parliament,
protection by the “great writ” of habeas corpus, and could expect a jury trial
in the event of being charged with a crime, In addition, by the terms of the
Bill of Rights of 1689 were guaranteed the right to bear arms, petition the
Crown for a redress of grievances, and be free from cruel and unusual
punishment. None of these rights, however, were accompanied by formal
documentation on an individual level. There were no cards or certificates by
which one could assert their citizenship if needed, and the whole concept
wasn’t really suited to operate outside of a fairly condensed geographic area. This
could, and did, create problems. If a British merchant, for example, moved to
the French city of Nantes, in Brittany, they would effectively be forced to
give up a number of their rights. They would not be able to vote in
Parliamentary elections, and would be subject to French law in their day-to-day
life. They would still be a British citizen, or course, but their ability to
exercise the associated rights would be constrained by any number of practical
limitations. No doubt this would seem entirely natural. Having left the green
fields of England for a foreign land, in which foreign people speak foreign
languages and recognize foreign laws, one could not reasonably expect
Parliament to hold any legal or social standing.
Now
imagine that same British merchant had departed for Boston instead of Brittany.
Though he would be three thousand miles away instead of five hundred, he would
similarly be unable to participate in Parliamentary elections. He may still
expect the monarch to hear his petitions, but the time between sending them and
receiving a reply would have increased dramatically. He would find himself
subject to the laws of Massachusetts, in the main, and yet the reach of
Parliament would find him still. Though the people of British America made it
quite clear in the 1760s and 1770s that they were generally unwilling to render
direct taxes to British authorities, they were far more amendable to British
laws that attempted to use taxation as a means of regulating commerce. The
Molasses Act (1733), for instance, placed a tax of six pence per gallon on (coincidentally)
molasses that was imported to the American colonies from any non-British
territory. Intended to shore up the economies of the various British
possessions in the West Indies by making their product cheaper than that
formerly supplied by Dutch, Spanish, or French Caribbean colonies, the act
remained in force until it was replaced by the Sugar Act in 1764. American
colonists regularly flouted its provisions, and thanks to the efforts of a
fleet of intrepid smugglers maintained a thriving molasses trade with the French
and Dutch West Indies. All the same, its imposition did not result in the kind
of vociferous outrage that the Stamp Act and Townshend Duties later elicited.
Confronted by this at least outward acquiescence to certain acts of Parliament,
Americans’ seemingly contradictory insistence on being taxed only by their
local legislators, and their generally high degree of affection for British
culture and British custom, our immigrant British merchant could be forgiven
for being a little confused. Was he still in Britain, or a foreign country? Did
British law apply in America, or not? Was he still entitled to all the rights
of British citizenship, or had he given them up when he stepped off the dock in
Portsmouth?
Though
doubtless somewhat more certain of the answers than our theoretical Boston
transplant might have been, James Wilson posed a similar set of questions in
the thirty-seventh paragraph of Considerations.
Parliament, through the passage of the Stamp Act and the Townshend Duties, had
claimed the right to tax the people of British America. Because Parliament was
composed of the elected representatives of the British people, it thereby
followed that the general population of Great Britain considered themselves in
some sense superior to their American cousins. Legislators in colonial
Massachusetts would be hard-pressed to attempt to collect tax revenue from the
people of London, yet it was evidently acceptable for the latter to claim a
right to the monies of Boston, or Philadelphia, or Williamsburg. This, Wilson
reasoned, was a puzzling notion. “What acts of ours has rendered us subject to
those, to whom we were formerly equal?” he asked.
Is British
freedom denominated from the soil, or the people of Britain? If from the
latter, do they lose it by quitting the soil? Do those, who embark, freemen, in
Great Britain, disembark, slaves, in America? […] Whence proceeds this fatal
change?
Wilson, as the substance of Considerations made quite clear, was of
the opinion that British liberties transcended geography –the same rights
applied to those who had left Britain behind and could no longer be expected to
participate in the domestic political process. Nevertheless, the questions he
asked in the thirty-seventh paragraph of his 1768 pamphlet were likely more
difficult to answer than he let on.
British/English political and
legal customs, as generally understood at the end of the 18th
century, were not well-adapted to the reality of a widely dispersed empire.
While Common Law jurisprudence and jury trials may have been amenable to
importation into foreign climes, British political culture was very much
centered on a centrally-located and sovereign Parliament. Leaving Britain
therefore meant, in a very practical sense, leaving the protection and the
authority of Parliament behind. Colonial legislatures, in places like
Massachusetts, or Virginia, or Jamaica, were designed in large part to act as
substitutes for the British assembly from which they derived. In keeping with
the common understanding of British liberties, they were elected, held sole
authority over direct taxation, and served to guard the rights of the people
against the prerogatives of Crown-appointed governors. While it is unlikely
that any colonial assembly in the 18th century British Empire would
have claimed to possess sovereign authority equal to Parliament, the practical
reality was very much in that vein – Parliament looked to the people it
directly represented in Britain, and the various far-flung assemblies did the
same for their constituents, in the style and adhering to the customs that
Westminster had set. By attempting to make law for the American colonies in the
same way it made law for Britain itself, however, Parliament effectively
shattered this pragmatic and mutually tolerable status quo and called into
question the compatibility of British citizenship with the physical reality of
the contemporary British Empire.
It was quite perceptive of Wilson
to ask his audience whether British liberties derived from the soil of Britain
itself or from the blood of its inhabitants. Prior to the era of widespread
European exploration – beginning roughly in the late 15th century –
this distinction didn’t really exist. Few people of English descent lived
outside of England before the era of European colonialism, and those that did
were subject to the laws of whatever realm, kingdom, or empire served as their
host. The emergence of an English (later British) empire in the 16th,
17th, and 18th centuries rendered this simplistic
definition invalid by dispersing English/British people across distant
territories over whom no established political entity laid claim. People born
of British parentage in these colonial territories were thus unusual in the
history of Western civilization by being native subjects of a European power
without necessarily being citizens. The difference, in the parlance of the 21st
century, was essentially between citizenship by birth and citizenship by
descent. The implication of this dichotomy was that a choice for one or the
other, as Wilson observed, would either expand or contract the number of people
who could claim the associated legal and political rights. If British liberties
sprung from residing in Britain itself, then those who departed to found
colonies in North America, the West Indies, or Asia were in effect creating new
nations, derived from Britain but legally and political independent. If, on the
other hand, British liberties were the birthright of every person born of
British blood, the geographic scope of Parliament’s authority was theoretically
limitless, provided the logistical challenges of administering a global empire
could be surmounted.
Unfortunately, the British Empire
of the late 18th century was as limited as any of its European
rivals by contemporary communication technology from guaranteeing every one of
its subjects the same political liberties. A resident of 1760s Boston simply
could not be represented in Parliament – the distance between Massachusetts and
England was too vast, as was the time involved in transmitting information
between them. The people of British America was still subjects of the British
Crown, still held true to the foundational rights and customs of British legal
and political culture, but they were functionally incapable of enjoying all of
the privileges that residents of Britain proper had come to expect. Though
Wilson did not admit as much, or at least did not intend to, Considerations does seem to draw out this incongruity. The
British liberties that 18th century Americans so dearly cherished
may simply have been incompatible with their collective status as the
caretakers of a distant colonial outpost. However much they thought of
themselves as the inheritors of the Magna Carta, the Glorious Revolution, and
the Bill of Rights, Parliament could not belong to them like it belonged to
their British cousins, or serve their collective interests quite so directly.
Colonial assemblies could, and did, serve as adequate surrogates, but only as
long as Parliament itself respected their jurisdiction. In the event that the
assembled delegates to Westminster attempted to extend their authority beyond
what was mandated by prudence and practicality – an occurrence Wilson seemed to
think inevitable, given that, “Parliaments are not infallible; they are not
always just” – a constitutional crisis would appear to be the inescapable
result.
It bears repeating that this was
not the point Wilson was trying to make in Considerations.
By and large, he seemed to hold that the preservation of the status quo – a
firm division between the domestic authority of Parliament and the colonial
legislatures – would mend whatever rift the passage of the Stamp Act and the
Townshend Duties had created. The people of British America were loyal subjects
to the Crown, he repeated more than once, and held dear the liberties and
customs that their forebears had handed down. It was indeed for this reason
that their ire had been provoked – Parliament had violated in America what it
had been created to protect in Britain. Understand this, he counselled, and
there could be no question as to the rightness of the American position. All
the same, the pamphlet he drafted to explain this position, and the reasoning
he deployed therein, suggests that a settlement between Parliament and the American
colonies may not have been sustainable. Adhering to the sense of reason that
grounded his method of inquiry, Wilson hit upon the ambiguity that lay at the
core of 18th century notions of citizenship and its associated
privileges. Absent documentation to that effect, what made someone in the 1760s
a citizen of any realm or kingdom in particular? Could a person born outside
the traditional confines of an established political community expect to
exercise the rights of that community? Considerations
draws up just short of delving into these questions in a deep or systematic
way, but modern readers would do well to consider their implications.
The model of political
consciousness that had sustained the British Parliamentary system through civil
wars and numerous rebellions had begun to fragment by the late 18th
century. Though separated from the soil that had witnessed its evolution,
British rights culture flourished in the settler-colonies of North America, and
lost none of its vigilant character or its suspicion of arbitrary power. As
with their cousins in Britain proper, the people of British America expected
their governments to be accountable, restrained, and respectful of their
rights. They were, after all, British subjects, and such was their birthright.
But what did it mean to be British, and to hold fast to British liberties,
three thousand miles distant from the Crown and its government? If being
British was a consequence of the land beneath one’s feet, leaving the isles
practically and legally negated that status. If Britishness was, on the other
hand, something passed through the blood, how could one ever claim to leave
behind the authority and protection of Parliament?
The legal and
political assumptions held by men like George Grenville, Prime Minster during
the passage of the Stamp Act, or James Wilson, Scottish-born American colonist
and scholar, were not well-suited to answer these questions. They, and indeed
their entire socio-economic class, had been instilled with the bone-deep
conviction that the British were the freest people in the world, that their
freedom was grounded upon certain specific rights, and that protecting and
promoting those rights was the central purpose of government. But nothing in
their shared education seemed capable of resolving what was supposed to happen
when the political community that nurtured these core assumptions began to
grow, and divide, and create increasingly inaccessible sub-communities. If one
of these sub-units of the British cultural polity disagreed with a decision
made by the government of the mother country, which of them was supposed to
give way? Where the far-flung colonial populations spread across the British
Empire the equals of their cousins in Surrey, and Shropshire, and Coventry, or
were they subordinate to them? While maintaining that few events in the history
of human civilization can rightly be thought of as inevitable, this line of
inquiry – raised by James Wilson in his 1768 pamphlet Considerations – does seem to suggest that the American Revolution
was at least in part an outgrowth of a functional and philosophical incongruity
between contemporary British rights culture and the realities of global empire.
No comments:
Post a Comment