Demonstrating
once more that he held no cows to be sacred – at times even in the face of his
own rational self-interest – Thomas Jefferson also included provisions in his
draft constitution for Virginia that would have trifled with the ownership of
what was likely the single-most coveted commodity in colonial America: land. In
a society dominated by agriculture and economically dependent on its own
ability to produce large quantities of certain high-value crops, arable land
was widely viewed as the key to both economic well-being and individual
self-sufficiency. Additionally, because the franchise in many colonies was
qualified by property ownership (measured in acreage or tax value), owning a
given quantity of land was also the gateway to political participation. The
middling Virginia tobacco farmer and the yeoman homesteader in western
Pennsylvania alike could thus trace whatever prosperity they enjoyed to their
status as landowners, as could some of the wealthiest families in America whose
vast plantations and agricultural estates were objects of pride and envy. Attempting
to alter the manner by which property in 18th century America was
owned, distributed, sold, or inherited therefore entailed potentially effecting
the lives and livelihoods of people from across a wide swath of different
social and economic strata. Jefferson’s draft constitution for Virginia betrays
an evident intent to do just that within the confines of his home country, to
the end of addressing several of his own moral and philosophical concerns.
Before going any further, however,
it would perhaps be wise to take a moment and lay out a little background.
Though it would surely take more time than any of us have to spare to
adequately explore the history of land ownership in colonial Virginia, a few
key concepts and facts will hopefully suffice for the present discussion. It
would do well to note, for instance, that within the boundaries occupied by the
colony as of the turn of the 18th century, Virginia (approx. 100,000
square miles) encompassed more land than the whole of Great Britain (approx.
94,000 square miles). Furthermore, whereas land in Britain was often wrapped up
in feudal titles and monopolized by landlords, making it exceedingly difficult
for anyone who didn't stand to inherit to hope of owning the earth over which
they toiled, arable land in Virginia was both cheap and plentiful. For
potential settlers this was – it has been abundantly recorded – an incredibly
powerful incentive to migrate. Unfortunately for the average prospective
migrant, however, land in Virginia was not simply “up for grabs.” The directors
of the Virginia Company, who were solely responsible for administering the
colony and disposing of its resources under a Royal Charter granted in 1607,
set about capitalizing on the abundance of land and addressing the labour needs
of plantation agriculture (i.e. tobacco) by putting in place what was known as
the Headright system.
First authorized in 1618, this scheme
approved the granting of a 50 acre parcel of land to every immigrant who paid
their own way to Virginia, or to any investor who paid for their passage. New
arrivals in the latter group were thereafter customarily required to sign
articles of indenture for a period of five or seven years and work to clear and
improve the land of their benefactor until their contract expired. Because of
the relatively high cost of an Atlantic crossing, most immigrants brought to
Virginia under the Headright system fell into this category. Unable to acquire land
simply as a result of their arrival, they were forced instead to purchase homesteads
further into the colonial interior – where conditions were less forgiving,
Native raids were a common occurrence, and viable markets were very distant – once
their term of service was up. Overall, however, the exchange of land for labour
proved exceptionally beneficial for the financial health of the colony – and
for its corporate masters in particular, land being so much cheaper than
transportation fees. The system was, or course, not without its flaws. Potential
investors and ship captains are known to have cooperated in claiming headrights
for those who had paid their own way, or for more immigrants than had actually
arrived in a given shipment. As a result of these abuses, as well as of the
general preference the Headright system gave to those with wealth enough to
subsidize the peopling of Virginia, land in the colony came to be concentrated
through the 18th century in a fairly small number of hands. All the
same, headrights continued to be granted following the re-charter of Virginia
as a Crown Colony in 1620, and in time became the foundation upon which the
wealth of many of the colony’s most prominent families was built.
The society into which Thomas
Jefferson was born in the 1740s was very much the product of these earlier
immigration and land-distribution policies. Estates built up during the 17th
century had been passed down, subdivided, or enlarged, and the resulting class
of large-scale landowners effectively dominated the social and political
landscape. Seeking to fundamentally alter this rather rigid status quo, of
which he was very much a beneficiary, the Sage of Monticello inserted into his 1776
draft constitution two specific clauses intended to address who owned land and
what they were permitted to do with it. The first stated, following a sentence
which declared that all forfeited or otherwise unaccounted for lands were to be
appropriated by the state government, that,
Every
person of full age neither owning nor having owned 50 acres of land, shall be
entitled to an appropriation of 50 acres or to so much as shall make up what he
owns or has owned 50 acres in full and absolute dominion. And no other person
shall be capable of taking an appropriation.
While this perhaps doesn’t qualify
as wealth redistribution, it certainly would have resulted in a fundamental
reordering of Virginia’s economic and political status quo. Bearing in mind
that the property qualification on the franchise that Jefferson described in
his proposed constitution required the possession of only ¼ of an acre in town
and 25 acres in the country, appropriations of the type described above would
have potentially entitled any citizen who desired to claim their 50 acres the
right to vote.
Furthermore, because Jefferson also
declared in the same document that, “Every person so qualified to elect shall
be capable of being elected,” the distribution of such parcels of land would
likewise have resulted in a much greater percentage of Virginia’s population
becoming eligible to serve in an office of state. The consequences of such an
expansion – in terms of who could vote and be voted for – would doubtless have
been considerable. Men customarily inclined by their circumstances towards
deference to their social betters would have been permitted to exercise the
same political rights upon the same terms as the wealthiest plantation owners.
Those accustomed to public service as an accoutrement of their wealth may have
consequently been forced to pay heed to the concerns of a much-enlarged voting public
and thereafter cultivate their support via the promotion of certain policies or
positions. This, combined with the potential influx of newly-landed men into
the General Assembly, would inevitably have wrought significant change upon the
nature of political discourse in Virginia, the issues most commonly discussed,
and the social and economic perspectives in evidence. In all likelihood, this
was what Jefferson intended.
As previously discussed, the Sage
of Monticello often demonstrated in his writings an ardent desire to protect
and promote the rights of the common citizen and ensure that government always
fostered their ambitions rather than its own. Empowering the most responsive
branch of Virginia’s General Assembly, as he attempted to do in his 1776 draft
constitution, was one way to accomplish this. Rather than locate the seat of
power in a singular, unelected governor, as had been the custom, it was instead
to be distributed among the members of a lower house elected on a yearly basis.
Because this in itself would have amounted to very little so long as the
electorate itself and the slate of candidates remained unchanged, Jefferson
also intended to ease the franchise qualification so that more Virginians could
vote and receive the votes of others than ever before. His proposal to grant 50
acres to every citizen who desired it, or so much as to raise their lifetime
total ownership to 50 acres, was very much in this same vein.
Even accepting that many
potential claimants who owned land in excess of 25 acres but less than 50 would
already have qualified for the franchise and to stand for office without any
additional grants, there must also have existed – otherwise it would seem
rather odd to even make the offer – a sizeable number of people living in
Virginia who owned no land at all as of 1776. Their voices and perspectives
were thus entirely unknown within the contemporary political scene, and their
government almost completely ignorant of their needs, concerns, or convictions.
These people – laborers, city-dwellers, and artisans, among others – would have
been permitted to instantly join the political class by accepting a grant of
land from the state, thus at a stroke vastly increase the ability of Virginia’s
government to truly speak for the citizens it claimed to serve. In time, Jefferson
likely hoped that these newly-landed individuals would abandon whatever
instinct they possessed to defer to their social betters as land ownership and
political participation became the norm rather than the exception. Able for the
first time to engage in public service alongside the scions of some of
Virginia’s wealthiest families, it no doubt seemed inevitable to the sage of
Monticello that existing social barriers would gradually break down and give
way to a far more egalitarian social structure than that which dominated the
colonial era.
Granted, the distribution of land
that Jefferson proposed in his draft constitution would not have altered the
fact that certain families in Virginia were far wealthier than others. Nor
would it have ameliorated all of the advantages, material and social alike,
that said families enjoyed. But at the very least it would have served to
narrow the gap between the “Haves” and “Have-Nots” in the Old Dominion, as well
as potentially broaden the realm of public discourse and promote a stronger
sense of political awareness among the general population. Being able to vote
and stand for election where they hadn’t before, it’s likely that many
Virginians would have been compelled to take a greater interest in the affairs
of state that now formed a part of their responsibilities. The emergence of a
new political class – of small-scale farmers, workers, and artisans of limited
means or education – would accordingly seem to be a potential result of this
expansion of the public sphere, though it’s hard to say if this was Jefferson’s
intention.
In spite of his lifelong advocacy
for the prerogatives of the common citizen, Thomas Jefferson’s opinion of the
suitability of the average American to hold political office was decidedly
mixed. Like many of his contemporaries among the Founding Generation, the Sage
of Monticello nurtured the underlying assumption that public service was the
preserve of a certain class of men – customarily defined by their education,
character, and wealth – who were best suited them to the pressures and concerns
of “great matters of state.” While he may have been willing to expand this
criteria of suitability to more generally include those who owned land in their
own right, in was only in later life that he began to support universal male
suffrage as the basis of political participation. Though much of the rhetoric
he deployed and many of the policies he endorsed did seem intent on actively empowering
the average, uneducated, middling citizen, it nonetheless represents a
potential misunderstanding of Jefferson to conclude from the above-quoted
passage that he was unreservedly in favor of seeing butchers, shop-keepers, and
frontier homesteaders striding about the halls of power. Or perhaps it might be
fairer to say, in light of the property qualifications his draft constitution
embraced, that he would have been willing to see the butcher or the shopkeeper
take their place in the General Assembly, but only once they had proven their
responsibility, independence, and investment in the community by becoming
landowners.
Key to understanding this
somewhat rigid attachment to property – and in turn the logic behind some of
the provisions included in his draft constitution for Virginia – is Jefferson’s conception of what constituted
an ideal republican citizen, the importance of personal autonomy and
independence, and the theoretical root of individual virtue. The ability of a
republic to survive the tumults of popular rule while staving off corruption, Jefferson
argued, lay in the virtue of the individual citizen, and in their willingness
to hold their ministers to account and guard against the wanton abrogation of
certain fundamental rights. This virtue could best be guaranteed only if those
whose sovereignty was the basis of republican government – the voters – were
free from trifling dependencies or attitudes of deference that might otherwise
warp or distort their intentions. A shop-keeper in New York who owed money to a
Boston merchant, say, or a tenant-famer in Virginia whose meagre prosperity was
owed to the benevolence of his landlord were thus ill-suited, in Jefferson’s
opinion, to exercise the political responsibilities the public sphere demanded
of them. Only someone who owned the land from which they drew their livelihood
could be trusted to enjoy the full and free exercise of their judgement. Furthermore,
because the personal prosperity of a landowner was directly tied to their
property, and because that property formed an immovable part of a larger
community, it thus seemed quite clear to Jefferson that owning land demanded an
individual take an interest in the political and economic well-being of the village,
county, parish, district, or state in which they lived. Accordingly, Jefferson
considered the planter, estate owner, and yeoman farmer (i.e. those who engaged
in small-scale subsistence agriculture) to represent the ideal republican
citizen, while the merchant, banker, and urban laborer (who possessed moveable
property or no property) were fundamentally unsuitable.
By granting land to
members of this latter group – not enough to turn them into wealthy planters,
mind, but a sufficient amount to allow them to subsist by their own hand –
Jefferson doubtless hoped to convert a large percentage of Virginia’s
population into what he considered to be ideal republican citizens. Granting,
of course, that this theory of republican citizenship was just that – a theory
– thus making it difficult to say whether the land grants the Sage of
Monticello enshrined in his proposed Virginia constitution would have exerted
the effect he desired, the logic behind it certainly aligns with what would
become the Jeffersonian ideology. Key to this pattern of political thought –
whose heyday in the United States spanned from approximately 1800 to the
mid-1820s – was the toweringly idealistic and maddeningly vague notion that
America was destined to form, as Jefferson wrote to James Madison in 1809, “An
empire for liberty as [man] has never surveyed since the creation [.]” This
empire, discussed at lengths in weeks past, was to be a community of conviction
and principle rather than power, and its fundamental basis – its smallest, and
yet most important constituent unit – was to be the meagre yeoman farmer whose
property was (again, in theory) the foundation of his virtue, and who would
have guarded against violations of the public good in the same breath that he
defended the land upon which he lived. While it cannot be denied that there is
a great deal more to the Jeffersonian ideal than the championing of the yeoman
farmer, and that a great many years passed between the events of 1776 and the
ascendancy of this ideal as a political force at the dawn of the 19th
century, there would at least appear to be a seed of the Jeffersonian link
between land and citizenship in the above-quoted passage of the Sage of
Monticello’s draft constitution for Virginia. Said draft constitution therefore
potentially represents one of the first written expressions of a stream of political
thought that would go on to redefine the culture and government of the United
States at a crucial moment in its early history.
No comments:
Post a Comment