The fundamentally flawed nature of
strict constructionism as a doctrine of constitutional interpretation – at
least as it had been deployed since the 1820s – is made exceptionally clear
when one examines certain key aspects of the arguments put forward by John C.
Calhoun in his South Carolina Exposition and Protest. Notwithstanding whatever
it was that the Constitution actually said, Calhoun was a man of particular
convictions whose sympathies, in general, lay with the state governments rather
than the federal government. This had not always been the case, to be sure. As
aforementioned, he had spent the better part of the 1810s and 1820s arguing in
favor of national solutions to what he perceived to be national problems – i.e.
defense, infrastructure, commerce, etc. By 1828, however, his focus had shifted.
Having previously favored tariffs as a means of promoting the growth of
domestic industry, he now objected to them on the grounds that they enriched
certain states only by impoverishing others. The fact that Calhoun’s home state
of South Carolina had suffered economically as a result of the Panic of 1819
was doubtless the catalyst for this dramatic change of heart, though the arguments
which he began to deploy were broader than this might indicate. As it happened,
the doctrine of strict constructionism offered a ready-made solution for people
like Calhoun who quite suddenly found cause to favor the notion of a limited
national government. It emphasized the limited nature of federal power, played
down the scope of the Necessary and Proper Clause, and played up the importance
of the Tenth Amendment. That it was also straightforward, cohesive, and
possessed the imprimatur of such towering figures as Thomas Jefferson and James
Madison certainly did it no harm. Indeed, strict constructionism was almost exactly
what Calhoun needed. The only problem with it was in its inherently limited
scope of action.
This fact was plainly a problem for
Calhoun – whether he was willing to admit it or not – because the Constitution
alone could not supply what he really wanted. He believed, consequent to
successive federal tariffs that appeared to sacrifice the agricultural wealth
of the Southern states in exchange for bolstering the manufacturing wealth of
the North, that it was improper for the federal government to enforce such laws
as effected the various states unequally. A valid stance, to be sure, and one
which he was free to advocate. He was also of the opinion – separately, but for
much the same reasons – that the essential sovereignty of the states
unquestionably entitled them to the right to both assess the validity of
federal law and nullify the same in the event that state prerogatives were
threatened. Likewise, this was a perfectly reasonable opinion, and Calhoun most
definitely had the right to argue in its favor. Where both of these positions
became untenable was in Calhoun’s attempt to assert their validity – indeed,
their supremacy – via the doctrine of strict constructionism. He claimed, in
his Exposition and Protest, that the Constitution required the federal government
to act upon the states with equal effect. He also claimed, in that same
document, that the Constitution recognized the ability of the states to
essentially veto federal legislation. He argued forcefully for these positions,
and he argued at length. But in both cases, notwithstanding what he clearly
wanted to be true, he argued fundamentally in vain. The Constitution was not on
his side.
Consider, by way of example, the
first argument cited above. Chiefly in response to the passage of the Tariff of
1828 – essentially a piece of electioneering masterminded by Martin Van Buren
for the purpose of securing the election of Andrew Jackson as President –
Calhoun came to believe that it was inappropriate for the federal government to
pass such laws as had different effects on different states. As it stood, the
duties levied by the tariff on certain manufactured goods previously available
at very low prices from European suppliers was having the simultaneous effect
of bolstering Northern industry – by way of eliminating competition – at the
same time that it forced Southern agriculturalists to pay higher prices for the
processed materials they required. The result was unambiguous: an increasing
loss of Southern wealth and an increasing gain in Southern resentment. To
Calhoun’s thinking, this could not be allowed to continue, if for no other
reason than that such inter-sectional animosity was fundamentally unsustainable.
Attempting to communicate this point, he offered the following explanation. “If
they, by superior capital and skill,” he wrote, referring to the Northern,
increasingly industrialized states,
Should keep down successful
competition on our part, we would be doomed to toil at our unprofitable
agriculture, selling at the prices which a single and very limited market might
give. But, on the contrary, if our necessity should triumph over their capital
and skill--if, instead of raw cotton, we should ship to the manufacturing
States cotton yarn and cotton goods, the thoughtful must see that it would inevitably
bring about a state of things which could not long continue. Those who now make
war on our gains, would then make it on our labor. They would not tolerate,
that those, who now cultivate our plantations, and furnish them with the
material, and the market for the products of their arts, should, by becoming
their rivals, take bread out of the mouths of their wives and children.
It may well have been the case that
the emergence of such domestic, economic rivalries was functionally inevitable.
Different regions of the country had different resources at their disposal,
different strengths, and different traditions of labor and capital. And though
all of them were ultimately tied into the same global market and subject to the
same fluctuations of supply and demand, it was likely bound to be the case that
at some point the success of one region might come at the expense of another.
Whether or not it fell to the federal government to prevent such an outcome remains,
to this day, something of an open question. But Calhoun, for his part, believed
it was at the very least incumbent upon federal authorities not to encourage
the emergence of the same. The situation created by the Tariff of 1828, he
avowed, would have exactly this effect. “If not arrested,” he wrote, it must,
“Bring the country to this hazardous extremity [.]” For that reason, the terms
of the tariff must not have been allowed to persist. Based on the core
principles of compact theory, this assertion would seem logical enough on its
face. If, as compact theory asserts, the United States of America –
specifically under the auspices of the US Constitution – was formed by the
states for the purpose of allowing them to accomplish together what they could
not accomplish separately, then it certainly stood to reason that federal laws
which encouraged the formation of inter-state economic rivalries were
fundamentally self-defeating.
Granted, the notion
of “the greater good” does form some part of how compact theory functions. Inasmuch as it holds to the idea that the
utility of the majority should generally come before the objections of the
minority, compact theory does make some allowance for ignoring dissent. There
would seem to be limits, however, to how far this principle extends. A majority
of seventy percent would seem to occupy a different moral dimension than a
majority of fifty-one percent. If thirty percent of a community disagrees with
an action to be undertaken by the same, it might reasonably be argued that
giving in to the demands of this minority would represent a greater injustice
than would obeying the will of the much larger majority. If, however, fifty-one
percent of that same community feels one way and forty-nine percent feels
another, the path of justice is not to clear. As compact theory would have it,
a minority of forty-nine percent is not in a position to be very well served by
the community to which it belongs, and might indeed be better off departing
altogether and forming a separate community of its own. This principle, no
doubt, is what Calhoun was driving at with the explanation cited above. There
may indeed have been a greater good that the federal government was bound to
serve, but a tariff which essentially pitted one half of the union of states
against the other plainly failed to fulfill this mandate. And if it did, then
it could serve no purpose which the union of states was bound to recognize.
Again, as far as theory goes, this is all
fairly reasonable. If Calhoun truly believed that federal laws which,
notwithstanding their stated purpose, ultimately served to pit different
sections of the American republic against each other were incompatible with the
very existence of a union of states, that was his argument to make. Flawed
though this position may have been upon certain points, it nevertheless took as
its central focus a series of questions which will never cease to be of
enduring relevance within the realm of American political philosophy. Namely,
what is the purpose of the United States of America, whom does it serve, and to
whom is it accountable? Unfortunately for Calhoun – and indeed for all those
who have since followed in his footsteps – he did not stop at merely seeking an
answer. Rather, by way of the aforementioned theory of strict constructionism,
he sought to offer a potential solution; an explanation of the relationship
between the union of states and its constituent parts which he believed would
make clear how the thing had originally been constructed and how, in practice,
it was supposed to function. “The Government,” he wrote, referring to the
explicit terms of the United States Constitution,
Is thus positively restricted to the
exercise of those general powers that were supposed to act uniformly on all the
parts--leaving the residue to the people of the States, by whom alone, from the
very nature of these powers, they can be justly and fairly exercised, as has
been stated.
If the Tariff of
1828 was allowed to continue in force, therefore – creating, as it did, an
increasingly adversarial division between the Northern states and the Southern
states – “The relation of equality between the parts of the community,
established by the Constitution, would be destroyed [.]”
Curiously enough, Calhoun made no
mention in his Exposition and Protest of which specific clause of the
Constitution he believed “positively restricted” the federal government to act
in a uniform manner upon all the various states. Perhaps he felt that his
readers would not need to have the clause in question pointed out. Being, as he
was, patriots in good standing, they would already have the document memorized
and ready for recall at a moment’s notice. Then again, perhaps he felt that drawing
close attention to the specific clause in question would not have served his
purpose. Notwithstanding his claim of adhering closely and rigorously to the
plain text of the Constitution, it might have been the case in this instance
that he preferred to leave things a little vague so that he could argue more
flexibly as the situation at hand developed. In either case – indeed, in any
case – there is likely only one passage to which Calhoun could possibly have
been gesturing. Located in Section 8 of Article I – and functioning as a kind
of postscript to the taxing powers delegated to Congress – it states very plainly
that, “All Duties, Imposts and Excises shall be uniform throughout the United
States [.]” As Calhoun appeared intent on arguing, this clause invalidated
legislation like the Tariff of 1828 precisely because said tariff – by
promoting the growth of industry in the North at the same time that it made agriculture
in the South more expensive – did not act uniformly upon all parts of the
American republic. Convincing though this assertion doubtless appeared to many
of Calhoun’s countrymen, there was at least one thing wrong with it.
Consider, for a moment, what is
meant by the term “strict construction.” To apply a strict construction to the
Constitution of the United States is to take what is written therein as the
beginning and the end of the authority thereby envisioned. Reasonable
inferences can make no difference, nor external materials, commentaries, or
correspondence. The Framers may be in a position to clarify certain things – to
clear up lingering ambiguities by way of revealing the contents of certain
pertinent discussions – but this should not be permitted to displace the text
itself. What is written is the supreme law of the land, not to expanded upon or
used as the starting point for wild speculation, but to be understood and
adhered to as closely as is practicable. Not only does this approach represent
– to its advocates, at least – the most just form of constitutional
interpretation – placing, as it does, the text approved by common consensus
above the wheedling arguments of a handful of legislators and magistrates – but
also the most sensible. Who can say, after all, beyond a shadow of a doubt what
any framer of laws truly intended when they set about their work? Who can look
into the words on a page and see into the hearts of those who inscribed them?
Calhoun certainly appeared to be of this opinion. Early on in the text of his
Exposition and Protest he stated, by way of observing the difficulties inherent
in the long-term application of written statute, that, “The courts cannot look
into the motives of legislators. They are obliged to take acts by their titles
and professed objects, and if these be constitutional, they cannot interpose
their power [.]” Granted, he was not always happy with the results of this
arrangement, writing in the same paragraph that, “The Constitution may be as
grossly violated by acting against its meaning as against its letter [,]” but
in the end he nevertheless affirmed his belief in the efficacy of strict
constructionism. “Ours is not a government of precedents,” he thus declared,
“Nor can they be admitted, except to a very limited extent, and with great
caution, in the interpretation of the Constitution, without changing, in time,
the entire character of the instrument. The only safe rule is the Constitution
itself [.]”
With these declarations in mind, one is accordingly
given to wonder at the nature of Calhoun’s reading of the cited clause of
Article I, Section 8. All that the text in questions says is that, “All Duties,
Imposts and Excises shall be uniform throughout the United States [.]” The
terms of the Tariff of 1828 do not violate this stricture. They do not apply
only to the Northern states. They do not apply only to the Southern states.
They apply to all of the states to that point admitted to the American republic
without distinction, favor, or exception. To be sure, the effects of the Tariff
of 1828 were not uniform throughout the whole of the American Republic. Under
the terms thereof, Northern industrialists was free from having to compete with
their European counterparts while Southern agriculturalists were forced to pay
higher prices for manufactured goods. But the cited clause makes no mention of
the duties, imposts, or excises levied by Congress having to be uniform in
their effects. All that it says – reading it as plainly as possible, per the
core principle of strict constructionism – is that the duties, imposts, or
excises shall themselves be uniform. And so, indeed, they were.
No comments:
Post a Comment