Jackson’s expected veto of the re-charter
bill came three days after its approval in the House on July 10th,
1832. The plain fact of it was not in the least bit surprising. Notwithstanding
the earlier assurances of people close to Jackson that he was unlikely to
attempt completely destroying the Bank given its widespread popularity, his
ideological opposition to the very concept of central banking had never really
been in doubt. What was surprising – from the perspective of constitutional
law, at least – was the explanation he offered in addition to his stamp of
denial. Previous presidents, when they made use of the veto power granted to
them by Article I, Section 7 of the Constitution, did so explicitly out of
concern that the legislation in question was unconstitutional. This was
originally made explicit by George Washington when he vetoed the first version
of the Apportionment Act in April of 1792 and was repeated most recently by
James Monroe when he vetoed the Cumberland Road Bill in March of 1822. Jackson
himself had initially followed this example when he vetoed two other road bills
in May of 1830, but his approach to negating the Second Bank re-charter bill
was markedly novel. He did believe, for the record, that the creation of the
Second Bank of the United States by Congress in 1816, and its attempted
re-charter by Congress in 1832, were unconstitutional. Congress may indeed have
possessed the theoretical authority to create a national bank, he wrote, but
nothing in the Constitution gave a particular group of legislators the right to
prevent their successors from either dissolving that same institution or
chartering additional banks as they saw fit.
Where the logic of Jackson’s veto message
ultimately differed from the norm was in his assertion as to why his opinion of
a given law’s constitutional legitimacy should have made any difference at all
to its coming into force. The Supreme Court had already ruled in its decision
in MuCulloch v. Maryland (1819) that Congress did indeed possess the
constitutional authority to charter a national bank. The implications of the
Necessary and Proper Clause granted it this power, the majority opinion
declared, and it made no difference if the states took issue with the result or
not. But while the authority of the Supreme Court to make such declarations had
by that time been well established – pursuant, of course, to the principle of
judicial review as established in Marbury v. Madison (1803) – Jackson
nevertheless proceeded to affirm a different doctrine altogether in his message
accompanying the veto of the Bank bill. “The Congress, the Executive, and the
Court [,]” he asserted,
Must each for itself be guided by its
own opinion of the Constitution. Each public officer who takes an oath to
support the Constitution swears that he will support it as he understands it,
and not as it is understood by others. It is as much the duty of the House of
Representatives, of the Senate, and of the President to decide upon the constitutionality
of any bill or resolution which may be presented to them for passage or
approval as it is of the supreme judges when it may be brought before them for
judicial decision. The opinion of the judges has no more authority over
Congress than the opinion of Congress has over the judges, and on that point
the President is independent of both. The authority of the Supreme Court must
not, therefore, be permitted to control the Congress or the Executive when
acting in their legislative capacities, but to have only such influence as the
force of their reasoning may deserve.
There would seem
to be at least two points particularly worth noting from within this bizarre
interpretation of American constitutionalism. The first is Jackson’s apparent
disregard for the relationships which then existed between the various branches
of the contemporary federal government. Since Marbury v. Madison, every
Congress and every President had acknowledged and respected the unique
authority of the Supreme Court to review state and federal legislation for their
conformity to the text of the United States Constitution. More to the point, no
Congress and no President since Marbury had ever attempted to assert
that their interpretation of the Constitution was as valid and as binding as
that of the Supreme Court. Jackson’s assertion to the contrary – that Congress
and the President could determine for themselves whether a given law was
constitutional or not – was accordingly lacking in any kind of precedent. Given
that the United States follows the English Common Law tradition – wherein
precedent is paramount – this presented something of a quandary. If Jackson was
right, and the various branches of the federal government had always been free
to interpret the Constitution on their own initiative, why had the Supreme
Court alone exercised the authority to do so? Given the preponderance of
examples whereby the Court invalidated a state or federal law and Congress and
the President abided by the result, why should anyone call into question the
concomitant balance of authority? What did Jackson have on his side that might
have shed light on the origins of his conviction besides a vested interest in
the outcome of the present struggle? In point of fact, the President could
produce no evidence at all to support his extraordinary claim, nor give any
reason at all why the present instance should have given rise to such a drastic
reform of constitutional procedure while no past instance ever had.
The second element of the cited passage from
Jackson’s veto message whose implications ought to give anyone pause was the
President’s alarmingly use of an otherwise innocuous phrase. Affirming, as
seemed to be his primary objective, the supposedly equal right of Congress and
the President to judge of the constitutionality of a given piece of federal
legislation, Old Hickory notably declared that, “The authority of the Supreme
Court must not […] be permitted to control the Congress or the Executive when
acting in their legislative capacities [.]” The term “legislative capacities”
is the object at issue. The United States Congress naturally possesses a number
of legislative responsibilities. Not only is it responsible for passing regular
statutes – i.e. laws regulating this, defining that, or generally permitting or
prohibiting a given individual or corporate action – but it may also levy
taxes, establish government departments, and conduct investigations. The
Executive, by contrast, isn’t traditionally thought of as a legislative body.
On the contrary, and by most conventional interpretations, the Executive Branch
is not supposed to attempt to accomplish anything more beyond executing the
laws of the land. Presidents that meddle in the prerogatives of Congress accordingly
tend to be stoutly rebuffed, such attempts being roundly declared to be
unconstitutional. The presidential veto might perhaps be interpreted as
something of an exception, allowing a President, as it does, to weigh in on the
legislative process in a very profound sort of way. Upon consideration, there
would indeed seem to be arguments on both sides.
On one hand, because the President is
subject to election by the American people as a whole while the various members
of Congress stand for election in discreet districts or within the states, it
might reasonably be argued that the presidential veto represents a third layer
of legislation discretion beyond that offered by the House and the Senate.
Whereas the House stands in for the American people as members of specific
geopolitical communities, and the Senate stands in for the American people as
organized into the various states, the President might conceivably be said to
stand in for the American people as an undifferentiated mass. Indeed, the President
would seem to be the only office within any branch of any government in the
United States of America that could reasonably claim to perform this function. Bearing
this in mind, it might in fact be the case the that Executive Branch of the
United States government does – and did, in 1832 – possess at least one
“legislative capacity,” to be exercised with as much discretion as those of the
House or the Senate. The only problem with this interpretation of the
significance of the presidential veto, of course, is that it is plainly not
what the Framers intended.
This isn’t to say, of course, that the
meaning intended by the Framers should in all cases override the meaning held
by those of us who yet live and breathe. A wise man – albeit one who did not
always heed his own advice – once keenly observed on this very subject that, “It
is ultimately the provisions of our laws, rather than the principal concerns of
our legislators, by which we are governed.” That being said, where the
intentions of the Framers as to a given aspect of their work are clear and
explicable, prudence would seem to dictate that they be afforded their just and
proper weight. Bearing that in mind, certain excerpts from the debates which
took place over the course of the Philadelphia Convention on the subject of the
executive veto – as recorded by Virginia delegate James Madison, no less –
would seem to warrant consideration. Specifically, it is the debate that took
place on September 12th, 1787 which merits scrutiny at the present
moment. The discussion at hand between the assembled delegates concerned the
relative strengths and weaknesses of either a 2/3 or a 3/4 majority for the
purpose of overriding an executive veto. Some, like New Yorkers Alexander
Hamilton (1755-1804) and Gouverneur Morris (1752-1816), believed that 2/3 was
insufficient to prevent Congress from coming to dominate the office of
President. Others, like South Carolina’s Charles Pinckney (1757-1824) and the aforementioned
James Madison, held to the opposite view, arguing that a threshold of 3/4 would
place too much power in the hands of too few people to impede the proper
function of the proposed national government. In the end, of course, the issue
was settled in favor of a 2/3 majority, at which point the discussion moved on.
But in the moment, as each side sought to clarify their respective positions, two
delegates in two separate comments made it known quite clearly the specific
functions which they intended the existence of the veto to perform.
The first of these comments was submitted
by Massachusetts delegate Elbridge Gerry (1744-1814), future Vice-President and
namesake of the term “Gerrymander.” Evidently seeking to remind his colleagues
of the nature of the object over which they disagreed, he helpfully explained to
all those present that, “The primary object of the revisionary check of the
President is not to protect the general interest, but to defend his own
department.” The second comment, offered shortly thereafter by Madison himself,
echoed this sentiment while adding an additional stipulation. “The object of
the revisionary power is twofold [,]” Madison affirmed. “1. to defend the
Executive Rights 2. to prevent popular or factious injustice.” Granting that
the discussion at hand was not concerned with the nature and purpose of the
executive veto as much as it was with the conditions under which the same might
be overturned, it is nonetheless worth remarking upon that no one present
disagreed with either of these descriptions. In consequence, while there might
not have existed a consensus amongst the assembled delegates as to the
mechanics by which the executive veto was bound to operate, there seems to have
been complete agreement as to the functions that it was supposed to perform. On
the one hand, as per Gerry and Madison, it was intended to aid the Executive
Branch in protecting itself from having its rights and responsibilities eroded
or destroyed by the Legislative Branch. And on the other, as per Madison alone,
it was supposed to offer the Executive Branch some means of countering the
influence of majority factions within the Legislative Branch bent on subverting
the basic principles of justice.
Returning to the subject of Jackson’s veto
message of July 10th, 1832, his assertion that the Chief Executive
possessed a “legislative capacity” which should have been free to operate
independently of the judgement handed down by the Supreme Court should now
appear to be especially curious. As the records of the Philadelphia Convention
debates make quite clear, the Framers did not intend for the executive veto to
in any way constitute a legislative function. Jackson seemed intent on denying
this, claiming as he did that it was the responsibility of the President to
weigh in on the constitutionality of all laws submitted for his signature. But
as Elbridge Gerry noted – and as none of his colleagues denied – “The primary
object of the revisionary check of the President is not to protect the general
interest, but to defend his own department.” As Jackson was not endeavoring to
protect the rights of his office when he vetoed the re-charter of the Second
Bank of the United States, he must therefore have been inventing a
responsibility which the Founders never intended. In light of his established
convictions, this was a strange position to take.
Jackson claimed to be a strict
constructionist in the mold of Thomas Jefferson. He claimed to favor the rights
of the states over those of the federal government. Both of these aspects of
his character would seem to preclude articulating a much broader vision of
executive responsibility than any of his predecessors had every attempted. But
Jackson was also an ardent critic of the Supreme Court as it then existed. Like
Jefferson, he was not amenable to the notion of unelected jurists striking down
laws enacted by the elected representatives of the American people. Better, he
seemed to believe, that such power lay in the hands of the President, being the
only office in the whole of the American republic which, by definition,
possessed the confidence of the whole of the American electorate. Perhaps this
conviction did put a gloss on certain aspects of the Constitution which the
Framers had never intended, and perhaps it did lend the Executive Branch a
scope of action far beyond its established limits. But Jackson – again, like
Jefferson – didn’t seem to be the kind of person who worried very much about
the means he was forced to utilize if he believed that the ends were suitably
justified. He knew what needed to be done, and damned if he was going to let
anything stop him from doing it.
The broader philosophical implications of
Jackson’s veto message were something of an academic point at the time of its
publication, of course. As the President of the United States, pursuant to
Article I, Section 7, he could veto legislation submitted by Congress based on
whatever criteria he deemed relevant. The text in question makes this clear
enough. “Before the Same shall take Effect,” it says, referring to bills
approved by both houses of Congress, they “Shall be approved by him, or being
disapproved by him, shall be repassed by two thirds of the Senate and House of
Representatives [.]” The Framers certainly had a specific meaning in mind when
they devised this procedure – as the discussion above should have made clear –
but this meaning is entirely absent from the Constitution itself. Jackson’s
veto of the Bank bill, therefore, while philosophically at odds with the
principles held by the Framers, was nonetheless entirely in keeping with the
law of the land. The supporters of the re-charter effort naturally claimed
otherwise. Daniel Webster maintained that Jackson’s assertion that the
President could declare a law that had been passed by Congress and approved by
the Supreme Court unconstitutional was wholly without basis in law or fact,
while Henry Clay went so far as to assert that such arbitrary interference by
the Executive Branch into the work of the national legislature represented an imminent
threat to representative government in America. But while their outrage was
loudly and emphatically expressed, Jackson’s opponents behaved as though they
had no choice but to abide by the aforementioned constitutional procedure.
Jackson’s veto having sent the re-charter bill back to Congress, the supporters
of the Second Bank worked tirelessly to amass the requisite 2/3 majority in
each house. By July 13th, however, with nothing more than a simple
majority in the Senate to show for their efforts, Jackson’s veto was formally
sustained. The Second Bank of the United States was effectively dead in the
water.
The general election that followed at the
end of 1832 was unsurprisingly characterized by both the Democrats and the
National Republicans as a referendum on Jackson’s treatment of the re-charter
bill and the Second Bank. As far as Jackson and his supporters were concerned,
the contest at hand was one between Jacksonian democracy and the rule of
bankers and financiers. Biddle and the Second Bank were decried in Democratic
newspapers as purveyors of corruption whose only aim was to enrich a handful of
well-placed individuals while the American people at large worked themselves
ragged just to survive. By stymieing the re-charter effort, these publications
went on to declare, Andrew Jackson had thus struck a blow for the liberty of
the common man and demonstrated once again his dedication to equality and his
abiding disdain for special interests. Notwithstanding the advice he received
to the contrary, Biddle provided ample fodder for these efforts by spending
widely and generously in an attempt to secure Jackson’s defeat. No longer
having to rely on mere rumors of malfeasance, Jackson was accordingly furnished
with all the evidence he could ever have desired that the Second Bank really
was being used by its directors to interfere in the democratic process.
The National Republican response to these
accusations – substantially convincing as they were – was comparatively
somewhat dry and academic. Clay and his fellow partisans made as much hay as
they could of Jackson’s often imperious behavior, his evident disregard for the
precedents of his office, and the implications which seem to accompany the
sentiments expressed in his aforementioned veto message. The National
Republican press depicted Jackson as a tyrant, and political cartoons portrayed
his as a scepter-wielding monarch. In the end, however, these kinds of
accusations could only go so far. At the time that Jackson was running for
re-election in the waning months of 1832, all that he had done to cause his
opponents to declare him a despot was veto a piece of federal legislation. The
accompanying rationale was certainly worrying, particularly as it threatened to
make the Executive Branch substantially immune from having its authority
checked or curtailed, but the President’s actions were thus far entirely in
keeping with the law of the land. Jackson could, at his own discretion, veto
any bill that was placed before him. The Constitution gave him that power. And
while it had become customary that the Chief Executive only deploy the veto
when they believed a proposed law to be unconstitutional, the Constitution
itself offered no instruction either way.
The Second Bank, by contrast – and
specifically under the leadership of Nicolas Biddle – had interfered repeatedly in American domestic
politics. Bank loans and donations had financed the political campaigns of a
number of its supporters, members of Congress had been cajoled into publicly
defending its record, and tremendous amounts of its operating capital had been
spent on trying to defeat the candidate for President most hostile to its
continued existence. Jackson’s claims as to the powers of his office may indeed
have present the greater threat to American liberty if they were ever acted
upon, but thus far the Second Bank had already shown itself to be a significant
threat in practice. After first having bungled their response to the Panic of
1819, thus worsening and lengthening the economic downturn that inevitably
followed, its directors had had the temerity to attempt to buy the political
support which they felt would be needed in order to keep their prerogatives
from being compromised or curtailed. Did the American people ever benefit from
all this political wheeling and dealing? Well, yes and no. The Second Bank had
played a significant role in stabilizing the American economy in the 1810s and
in the latter half of the 1820s. This was no mean feat, to be sure, and one
which its supporters were right to point out. That being said, the Second Bank
had also often tended to function as an instrument of wealth perpetuation for
the lucky few who owned shares or had access to its capital. That the
democratic process suffered along the way did not speak well for the Bank’s
continued existence, regardless of the associated advantages to which its
supporters were quick to point.
The Democrats, in the end, won the war of
words. Notwithstanding all of the money that Biddle had spent trying to
convince the American people of the necessity of the Second Bank or the latent
tyranny of Jackson – or indeed, perhaps precisely because of it – the President
was re-elected to a second term in office. Nor was his victory a near thing, it
bears adding. Of the 286 electoral votes up for grabs, the victorious candidate
needed 144. The fringe Anti-Masonic and Nullifier candidates – each highly
regional in their respective appeals – collectively secured eighteen electoral
votes. Henry Clay, carrying six states, took 49 electoral votes. Jackson, with
sixteen states and over 700,000 popular votes – 54.2% of all votes cast – came
away with 219 electoral votes. As far as the Democrats were concerned, this
overwhelmingly positive result constituted a ratification of Jackson’s veto of
the Second Bank re-charter bill. And as far as Jackson was concerned, it
constituted a popular mandate to dissolve the Second Bank well in advance of
its pending expiration.
The reasoning for Jackson’s particular conclusion
was in many ways as pragmatic as it was principled. Biddle had already
demonstrated his willingness to use the resources of the Second Bank to
influence popular opinion and swing popular elections. It was accordingly
thought likely by Jackson and some of his more ardently anti-Bank supporters
that Biddle would respond to the defeat of his electioneering efforts by essentially
triggering a financial crisis for which Jackson would receive the blame. Understandably
desirous of preventing such an outcome, Jackson accordingly included a request
in his fourth State of the Union Address – delivered in December of 1832 – that
Congress investigate whether the federal government’s deposits were truly safe
in the hands of the Second Bank of the United States. The House of
Representatives responded in the affirmative, conducted its investigation, and
submitted a report for general approval in March of 1833. According to the
Democratic-controlled committee tasked with carrying out the inquiry by the
Democratic-controlled House – by a vote, it’s worth noting of 4-3 in favor –
the deposits were in fact perfectly and completely secure. Many Democrats
dissented from this finding, both from within the relevant committee and from
within the Democratic caucus more generally, but not to the extent that it was in
much danger of being rejected. Indeed, by a vote of 109-46, it was
overwhelmingly approved. This result understandably left Jackson both incensed
and newly determined. He was infuriated that his fellow Democrats should have
failed to grasp the opportunity to destroy the object whose continued existence
– or rather the threat thereof – had helped to secure their own elections. But
he was also now quite resolute in his conviction that this problem in
particular required his personal attention. Come hell or high water, he would
destroy the Bank himself.
No comments:
Post a Comment