While it is not
normally the purview of this series to draw direct comparisons between
philosophical or political concepts which were in circulation during the
American Founding and their 21st century equivalents – such things
seeming to be best understood within their own particular historical context –
it would be impossible to deny that part of what makes Cato V such an
interesting object of study is the degree to which it appears to anticipate and/or
converse with issues of enduring political significance. Certainly there were
others among the Anti-Federalists who waded into these very same waters in some
aspect or other of their many and various missives. The proper frequency of
elections, for example, was a relatively common point of reference for these
scribes, and one whose ongoing relevancy is demonstrated whenever circumstances
conspire to place national polls for a given office too close together for the
evident comfort of the public. Just so, as a great many of the Anti-Federalist
Papers declared that the essential rights of the American people would need to
be specifically enumerated before the proposed constitution might attain
ratification, so too do modern statesmen, scholars, and activists continue to
actively discuss the scope and nature of individual civil rights within such
ever-evolving contexts as privacy, sexuality, gender identity, and bodily
autonomy. Cato V cannot accordingly be thought of as unique by the mere fact
that it engages with certain issues whose relevancy in the political sphere has
not in the slightest bit diminished since 1787. Where Cato V does stand out,
however, is in the succinctness of its commentary and the degree to which its
author was able to present himself and his opinions in an exceptionally clear
and incisive manner. Connecting his work to modern conversations on the same
basic topic is thus so easy as to nearly accomplish itself.
Consider, by way
of example, two assertions which Clinton offered in the seventh and last
paragraph of Cato V. In the first, directed at yet another of what Clinton
considered to be the essential flaws embedded in the text of the proposed
constitution and addressed to the citizens of his home state of New York, he
declared that,
It is a
very important objection to this government, that the representation consists
of so few; too few to resist the influence of corruption, and the temptation to
treachery, against which all governments ought to take precautions -- how
guarded you have been on this head, in your own state constitution, and yet the
number of senators and representatives proposed for this vast continent, does
not equal those of your own state.
The second
assertion, located further on in the text of the same paragraph, expanded upon
this same idea by first posing a question – “Can it be asserted with truth,
that six men can be a complete and full representation of the numbers and
various orders of people in this state?” – and by then providing a counterpoint
to the supposed predilection of the Framers for a very “imperfect”
representation in the lower house of Congress. “The more complete it is,”
Clinton avowed, “The better will your interests be preserved, and the greater
the opportunity you will have to participate in government, one of the
principal securities of a free people.” As with elections to that same body of
legislators, Clinton was evidently of the opinion that more was always better than
less, inasmuch as he valued a very broad dissemination of political opportunity
and experience.
Upon due consideration, there would
seem to be at least two distinct ideas embedded in the passages cited above. On
one hand, Clinton evidently believed that the fewer representatives a given
community could elect the more likely it was that those representatives would
fall prey to, “The influence of corruption, and the temptation to treachery
[.]” Though he did not say as much, the logic behind this assertion appears to
be that, all things being equal, it is more likely that a dozen people
possessed of political authority – or enough of them to constitute a majority –
will fall prey to some kind of nefarious outside influence than will a hundred
in the same position. The more that power is diffused, therefore, the harder it
is for it to be corrupted. And on the other hand, Clinton also seemed to think
that a larger representation was superior to a smaller representation just on
general principles because it allowed for a more thorough understanding within
the legislative process of the issues facing specific communities and permitted
more people to either become directly involved in public affairs or to cherish
at least the possibility of the same. It was always better, in short, to send
one person to represent five thousand people than fifty thousand, and better
yet to send one to represent five hundred. The more that each individual
community within a given state could feel as though its interests were being
accounted for within the national legislative process, the healthier said state
will inevitably be.
These are, as aforementioned, exceedingly
relevant ideas within the present context of the early 21st century.
Political corruption – particularly within the legislative process – remains as
vital a topic of political debate now as when Clinton offered his take on it at
the end of the 1780s. Likewise, the ideal ratio of representatives to those
they represent is as yet a vital subtext of any of the conversations presently
taking place on the subject of electoral reform, government formation, or
apportionment. That being said, before digging into the relationship of Cato V
to any of these topics, a few facts and figures ought to be established. First,
it would seem a worthwhile exercise to verify the claim which Clinton appeared
to make in the text cited above. Addressing the citizens of the state of New
York, he claimed that, “The number of senators and representatives proposed for
this vast continent, does not equal those of your own state.” For the record,
as of the first decennial census mandated by the Constitution in the year 1790,
the total population of the United States of America was 3,929,214. Of that,
the population of New York on its own accounted for
340,120. As the American republic could accordingly claim to contain over ten
times as many people as the state of New York, Clinton would no doubt have
preferred that the combined representation of the American people in Congress
should accordingly exceed by a similar ratio that which the Empire State could
boast in its own legislative assembly. That this was not the case, he avowed,
should have been a source of grave concern, and reason enough to reject the
proposed constitution. In actual fact, however, the combined representation of
the upper and lower house of Congress did exceed that of the upper and lower
house of the New York General Assembly. Between the Senate and the House of
Representatives, Congress was comprised of a total of ninety-one legislators as
of the first presidential election in 1789. At that same time, in accordance
with the terms laid out in the state’s 1777 constitution, the upper and lower
houses of New York’s state legislature contained but eighty-nine total
delegates and senators.
While Clinton
was therefore technically incorrect in his assertion, the essential point he
was trying to make was nonetheless a valid one. Within the legislative assembly
of the state of New York circa 1787, the three hundred thousand people residing
therein were represented by almost ninety delegates between the upper and lower
houses. Of those, twenty-four sat in the state senate – averaging out to one
senator for every twelve-thousand people – and sixty-five sat in the assembly –
averaging out to one assemblyman for every five thousand people. By comparison,
looking at New York alone, the Empire State was to be represented in Congress –
as Clinton noted with evident disdain – by only eight delegates, two of which
were Senators – each representing the whole three hundred thousand – and six of
which were Representatives – each standing for over fifty-six thousand of their
fellow New Yorkers. Clearly, by sheer numbers alone, the New York State
Legislature would be better suited to translate the specific interests of the
inhabitants of the Empire State into actionable policy. This is, in some ways,
perfectly reasonable. The proposed national government claimed as its exclusive
preserve only such issues as would rise to the level of national significance –
i.e. foreign affairs, inter-state commerce, trade, and war, for example. It
would accordingly stand to reason that Congress would not need to account for
the particular needs of every distinct community in every state in the union.
Let New York’s eight delegates speak broadly to New York’s needs in a forum
design to handle issues of broad application, therefore, while that same
state’s fourscore and nine domestic legislators bring their expertise to bear
on matters of domestic importance.
There was just
one problem with the arrangement, however. While most of the communities within
the state of New York could reasonably claim the attention of a specific
assemblyman and senator – and while each of these delegates could reasonably
claim fairly detailed knowledge of the communities they claimed to represent –
the ratio of apportionment described by the proposed constitution simply
wouldn’t allow for the development of such fine-grained relationships between
representatives in Congress and their designated constituents. To put it
simply, one person might fairly claim to know the needs and interests of five
thousand, or even twelve thousand, much more readily than they could of fifty
thousand. And while this state of affairs might have been broadly acceptable
given the context noted above, it would necessarily entail glossing over the
opinions and priorities of great many distinct communities. New York City, for
example, though it’s 1790 population of 33,131 would arguably entitle it and
its environs to a whole Representative of their own in Congress, was at that
same time possessed of nine assemblymen in the lower house of the New York
State Legislature. In one sense, the Empire State’s largest city was lucky to
have a delegate almost completely to itself within the national political
sphere. But in another, it was at a disadvantage for having the interests of
its many and varied communities boiled down to a single voice when in other
contexts its diversity was far better accounted for.
New York City,
as it happened, was by far the most fortunate among the Empire State’s various
communities. Dutchess County – whose county seat, Poughkeepsie, was
incidentally the site of the New York Ratifying Convention – was also entitled
by its 1790 population of 45,276 to more or less claim a Congressman all to
itself. But in light of the fact that Dutchess was at that same time possessed
of seven assemblymen in the lower house of the New York State Legislature, this
could hardly have seemed like much of a boon. Whereas, on the floor of the
Assembly, towns that fell within Dutchess County like Rhinebeck, Fishkill, and Pine
Plains might have reasonably believed it possible to have an issue of
particular importance to them raised and debated, Congress would arguably have
presented a far less hospitable environment given the sheer size of the
district these selfsame towns would fall into. A representative who needs the
majority of the voters out of a constituency of five thousand people, after
all, would surely be more inclined to listen to petitions on behalf of even a
few hundred than would a representative whose constituency is ten times as
large. Granting that this state of affairs was more or less inherent to the
Framer’s vision of the manner in which a national government was supposed to
function – i.e. by way of abstraction – and bearing in mind that this is
essentially how the United States Government has successfully (?) functioned
since the 1780s, it was far from unreasonable at the time that Cato V was
published in 1787 to raise certain question as to the propriety of this or that
scheme of legislative apportionment. Certainly, there were other models then in
use which might have offered alternatives to that described by the proposed constitution.
The most obvious of these was naturally the one that Clinton mentioned
explicitly: the Parliament of Great Britain.
The
contemporary British government, of course, was organized along broadly
different lines to either the United States Government under the Articles of
Confederation or that described by the proposed constitution. The United States
was federal, Britain was unitary; the United States was a republic, Britain was
a monarchy. Nevertheless, the arrangement of responsibilities between the House
of Representatives, the Senate, and the President was similar enough to that
between the House of Commons, the House of Lords, and the Crown for an entirely
reasonable comparison to be made. As Clinton noted accordingly in the seventh
paragraph of Cato V, “The history of representation in England [is that] from
which we have taken our model of legislation [.]” Bearing this in mind,
consider the following. In 1790, the population of the Great Britain was
something on the order of sixteen million. The contemporary House of Commons
meanwhile contained some five hundred and fifty-eight seats. Granting that this
same body was at the time notorious for either over-representing or
under-representing an alarming number of communities, these figures average out
to about one Member of Parliament for every twenty-eight thousand people. This,
it bears noting, is something like half as many constituents as assigned to
every member of Congress according to the terms of the proposed constitution.
While Great Britain contained approximately four times the population of the
contemporary United States, it was therefore possessed of six times as many
representatives in the lower house of its national legislature. British
citizens, in short, were at least theoretically guaranteed substantially more
accurate and responsive political representation circa 1790 than their American
counterparts.
“Theoretically,”
of course, implies that the fact of the matter fell somewhat short of the
principle. As discussed at length in a previous series, the British House of
Commons as it existed at the end of the 18th century was an almost
comically unrepresentative body whose legislators as often owed their election
to privilege and patronage as to the support of a particular group of qualified
constituents. Ridings whose resident population had shrunk to a few hundred, or
in some cases even a few dozen, continued to elect two MPs at the direction of
whichever landowner had purchased the right to designate electors. Often as
not, these constituencies were centered on towns whose significance as market
centers dated from the Medieval era but whose importance as trade hubs had
severely diminished due to various economic, social, or even environmental
factors. By the same token, a number of major urban centers whose growth had
commenced only in the 17th or 18th centuries –
Manchester, for example, or Birmingham – were wholly without representation in
the House of Commons outside of that which belonged to the historical county that
they found themselves within. Granting that the average number of constituents
per Member of Parliament in the lower house of Parliament was indeed something
close to twenty-seven thousand as of the late 1780s and early 1790s, the
variation across constituencies could thus be frighteningly wide. Dunwich, for
example, which was abolished under the terms of the Great Reform Act (1832),
contained only thirty-two electors at the start of the 19th century
who between them sent two members to the House of Commons. Slightly less
egregious was the riding of Shaftsbury, whose population of 2,742 circa 1831
elected two MPs; it was later merged with several surrounding parishes until it
population reached upwards of eight thousand while its allotment of seats in the
House of Commons was reduced by half. And then there was Warwickshire, which by
the time of the Great Reform Act contained some three hundred thousand people
yet sent only two MPs to Westminster. The terms of said act accordingly split
the county into three ridings – one of which, the aforementioned Birmingham,
contained one hundred and forty thousand on its own – each electing two MPs.
It would of course have been terribly
unlikely – if not, indeed, wholly impossible – for George Clinton to have had
access to such precise franchise data at the time he penned Cato V in the
waning months of 1787. No doubt he knew – inasmuch as anyone can know a common
maxim to be true – that the House of Commons was at that time plagued by
corruption and underrepresentation. It might also be taken as a given that
anything he wrote which seemed to favor the model of representative government
then practiced in Great Britain did not constitute a tacit endorsement of the
accompanying institutional deficits which continued to plague that selfsame
system. Clinton’s evident intention, far from recommending every aspect of the
House of Commons as a guide for the modification of the Congress described by
the proposed constitution, rather seemed to be on the order of pointing up one
aspect in particular. Great Britain, it was true, possessed a substantially
larger population circa 1787 than did the United States of America, thereby
logically indicating that the number of MPs in the House of Commons was bound
to exceed the same count of Representatives in the lower house of Congress. But
while there were indeed more MPs than Representatives, there were also more MPs
per person in all of Britain than there was bound to be Representatives per
person in all of the United States. Why should this have been the case?
Notwithstanding the disparities which existed between one riding and the next,
why was the British government so generous in terms of elected representation
while the American government described by the proposed constitution promised
to be so stingy?
Clinton naturally
thought he had answers to these questions. It was his evident belief that the
Framers of the proposed constitution had made a point of allocating relatively
few Representatives per citizen – “The Number of Representatives shall not
exceed one for every thirty Thousand,” read Article I, Section 2 of the
document in question – so that the officers in question would be, “Too few to
resist the influence of corruption, and the temptation of treachery.” While
such suspicion is perhaps not all that surprising – some people being naturally
distrustful of power, and Clinton in particular having a fair bit to lose in
the event that his home state became suddenly subject to an empowered and
ambitious Congress – neither it is precisely explicable. That is to say, though
Clinton’s tendency to distrust the motivations of the Framers is more or less
in keeping with what we know about his character and interests, it would be
impossible to say for certain why he believed that the Framers specifically intended
for the House of Representatives to be especially vulnerable to corruption.
What does seem to bear examination, however, are certain of the implications of
Clinton’s all-but-stated belief that more representation was always preferable
to less, and that greater the number of representatives there are the less the
body to which they belong is susceptible to being compromised. While the
intervening centuries have not necessarily proven the author of Cato V to be
entirely wrong in holding to these convictions, they have certainly added their
share of complications. To place Clinton’s remarks in their proper context,
therefore, it would seem necessary to engage with the dimensions of
representative government whose existence he could not have predicted as well
as with those of which he believed himself especially well apprised.
No comments:
Post a Comment