While there was yet
some worth in this among Henry’s favored rhetorical techniques – in that
confrontation is sometimes necessary in a debate in order to break an impasse
or sort out the most basic terms of agreement and disagreement – there is
conversely very little that can be said in favor of this same orator’s apparent
propensity to mischaracterize the truth. This habit made itself known in
several forms across the length of his address to the Virginia Ratifying
Convention, often in an attempt to supplement an otherwise reasonable argument that
had no need of being bolstered. In some cases, the attempt was made to present
an ostensibly sensible-sounding fact – one which Henry’s cohorts would likely
have accepted without a second thought – whose veracity was in reality almost
impossible to confirm. By thus relying on the ignorance of his audience – or
their lack of resources, as the case may be – Henry was able to pass off a host
of false assertions as though they were the plain and simple truth. In other
cases, relying perhaps instead on the tension of the moment, or the suspicion
or the pride of his audience, he attempted to give the same presentation to
more obvious falsehoods. “Don’t pay attention to what my opponents are saying,”
Henry was effectively declaring with the latter technique, “Because you and I
know what’s really going on.” The former Governor of Virginia thus sought to
establish himself as a purveyor of hidden truths and the only trustworthy
participant in a conversation dominated by liars and artificers.
It was all hogwash, of course – to
borrow a charming colloquialism – but cunning hogwash all the same. Consider,
by way of example, an assertion which Henry made during his critical
examination of the amending formula described by the proposed constitution. As
mentioned previously, Henry was alarming by how few people would have actually
been required to deny an amendment for it to fail to achieve the force of law,
thus essentially placing the fate of the Constitution in the hands of a small
minority of the general population. “If, sir,” he lamented accordingly,
“Amendments are left to the twentieth, or tenth part of the people of America,
your liberty is gone forever.” As contemporary figures well affirm, this
represented a perfectly legitimate concern – if a statistically unlikely one –
and Henry was by no means behaving in a suspect fashion by attempting to alert
his countrymen to the same. But then, for whatever reason, he felt the need to
draw a comparison. “We have heard,” he continued,
That there
is a great deal of bribery practised in the House of Commons, in England, and
that many of the members raise themselves to preferments by selling the rights
of the whole of the people. But, sir, the tenth part of that body cannot
continue oppressions on the rest of the people. English liberty is, in this
case, on a firmer foundation than American liberty.
There was some
truth to this assertion, of course. The contemporary House of Commons was
notoriously – almost comically – corrupt, shot through with procedural
inconsistencies and rife with cronyism and entrenched venality. Whether a given
individual could vote or stand for election depended on where in Great Britain
they could claim to reside, electoral regulations were a confused and
contradictory muddle, and a number of seats in Parliament were the exclusive
possession of wealthy patrons who made a practice of either selling the right
of election or bestowing the office on a favored friend or relative. Thus, as
Henry rightly observed, did many members, “Raise themselves to preferments by
selling the rights of the whole of the people.”
But the former Governor of Virginia didn’t
stop at merely observing the sorry state of late 18th century British
democracy. “But, sir,” he instead went on to say, “The tenth part of that body
cannot continue oppressions on the rest of the people.” Granting that the
figure of “one tenth” was meant by Henry to form a rhetorical parallel with the
issues he had previously cited with the aforementioned amending formula, the
claim itself had no basis in fact. Neither Henry, nor any of his countrymen,
nor likely anyone in Britain with even an expert knowledge of the deficiencies
of the contemporary House of Commons could have said for certain how many seats
therein were subject to endemic corruption, what effect their presence had on
the ability of the voting public to see their will translated into legislation,
or what ratio of corrupt to non-corrupt ridings would have tipped the balance
in favor of the former. Such information simply wasn’t available in the 1780s,
in no small part because no one was particularly interested in collecting it on
a large enough scale to form any actionable conclusions.
This isn’t to say, mind, that the topic of
reform had never before entered into Britain’s national political discourse.
The adoption of universal suffrage – along with a great many other similarly
audacious proposals – had been passionately debated during the waning years of
the English Civil War (1642-1651), particularly by such factions of the
Parliamentary army as believed it essential while they yet controlled the reins
of power to “level” as much of British society as substantively possible. While
the emergence of Oliver Cromwell (1599-1658) as de facto sovereign of the
English Commonwealth in the early 1650s effectively dashed any such hopes in
the immediate, the state of corruption in the House of Commons remained
troubling enough to some portion of the British political establishment that
the issue reared its head again in the 1760s at the behest of William Pitt the
Elder (1708-1778) and in the 1780s at the hands of William Pitt the Younger
(1759-1806). Sincere though this father and son duo most certainly was to see
the so-called “people’s house” reformed to the point where it might actually be
said to reflect the will of the general British public, however, both men faced
impossibly long odds. Pitt the Elder, perhaps because he had himself been first
sent to Parliament as the Member for Old Sarum – arguably the most “rotten”
seat in all of Britain, controlled at that time by the Pitt family of Boconnoc,
Cornwall – and perhaps in recognition of the fact that there were many more men
of influence who had arrived in the House of Commons by the same means, declined
to suggest the elimination of the corrupted boroughs in question. Instead,
hoping to counterbalance what he regarded as the detrimental influence of the
borough ridings – a number of which, because of the way that they allocated
votes, were horrendously unrepresentative – by adding an additional seat to
each of the county ridings. Unsurprisingly, this proposal met with significant
resistance. Those in possession of borough ridings did not take well to the
notion that their influence needed to be actively decreased. Others held that
giving more power to the landed gentry who dominated the county ridings would
do little to counteract the tendency of Parliament to become a tool in the
hands of an interested few. The proposal accordingly failed to generate even
token legislation, and the issue of reform resumed its accustomed dormancy.
Pitt the Younger, though more successful –
and perhaps more tenacious – than his father at getting the prospect of
reforming the House of Commons a formal public hearing, likewise failed to
achieve even the modest program of reform which he believed it wisest to
pursue. Attempting initially, as a backbencher, to resurrect his father’s
proposal – an effort which, though it did come to a vote, ultimately went down
to defeat to the tune of 140 against – Pitt next proceeded as Prime Minister to
introduce a far more ambitious program in 1785 that would have eliminated the
representation of thirty-six rotten boroughs while also slightly extending the
electoral franchise in all that remained. While this latter effort represented
by far the most wide-ranging bid to alter the essential composition of the
House of Commons since the 1640s – a testament, to be sure, to the political
imagination of its author – it was perhaps for this exact reason that it could
not but have met with eventual defeat. Though 174 Members of Parliament voted
in its favor, 248 voted against. For the remainder of his term in office – the
first stint of which lasted from 1783 to 1801 – Pitt the Younger declined to raise
any further discussion of reforming the House of Commons.
The issue of Parliamentary corruption
having been essentially settled in Britain in 1786 for at least the next forty
years – until the first rumblings of the debate which would lead to the passage
of the Reform Act of 1832 – it would seem audacious indeed for Patrick Henry to
claim in 1788 to possess anything like a deep and precise knowledge of the
effects and significance thereof. The events which finally led to the first
successful act of legislative reform in British history took place over a
period of several years in the early 1830s, during which time a great deal of
information had to be gathered and collated so as to provide the authors of the
bill in question with a set of precise figures and proposals to be presented to
their fellow MPs. Only by the end of this process, therefore, could anyone on
Earth truly claim to know with a certainly how and to what extent the existence
of endemic corruption in the House of Commons had thus far affected the
business of Parliament. In the end, the terms of the Reform Act mandated the
total abolition of fifty-six boroughs, the reduction of a further thirty from
two seats in the House to one, and the creation of a further one hundred and
thirty seats divided among a number of otherwise unrepresented or
underrepresented counties and towns across England and Wales. Recalling that
Pitt the Younger’s 1785 plan called for the abolition of only thirty-six
boroughs, one is forced to wonder at the nature of the discrepancy. Where his
standards less stringent than those of his eventual successors? Did he
consciously restrain his attentions to only the worst cases so as not to lose
potential allies? Or did he simply lack the information that the later Reform
Act proponents ultimately had several years to gather and analyze? Likely the
answer embodies some combination of each of these factors. Sincere though he
surely was, Pitt the Younger also doubtless possessed canny enough political
instincts to know how far he could push a particular measure before it lost
even a hope of success. And he almost definitely possessed less and spottier
information than would his counterparts some four decades later.
Bearing all of this in mind, it would once
again seem eminently bizarre for Patrick Henry, some two years after Pitt the
Younger’s last effort at Parliamentary reform failed and on the entire other
side of the world, to speak with evident authority as to the nature and
implications of political corruption in the contemporary House of Commons. One-tenth
of that body, he said, could not “continue oppressions on the rest of the
people.” But how could he possibly have known that? On what data did he base
this statement? Maybe one tenth of the sitting members were exactly enough to
capture and hold the initiative of Parliament, particularly if the members in
question belonged to particularly influential families or factions. Or perhaps,
in a negative sense, one tenth of the sitting MPs could introduce enough delay and
sow enough chaos as to stymie the passage of otherwise salutary legislation.
Indeed, one tenth may have been more than enough, not that the figure itself
had any significance beyond what Henry gave it. By the reckoning of the authors
of the aforementioned Reform Act of 1832 – accepting, of course, that the final
terms of said act represented a compromise – one hundred and forty-three total
seats were abolished. As a percentage of the total number of seats then
allocated in Parliament – that being, as of 1831, six hundred and fifty-eight –
this would amount to just under twenty-two percent. Affirming, once again, that
this figure likely represents the most accurate contemporary understanding of
the depth of corruption within the House of Commons, Henry’s citation of one
tenth or ten percent would appear almost wholly nonsensical. That is to say,
even if a corrupt ten percent of the sitting members in the lower house of
Parliament could not, as Henry said, “continue oppressions on the rest of the
people,” the actual figure as of 1788 was likely closer to double that.
Notwithstanding his need to quote a figure
that had no particular connection to reality, Henry’s comparison of the corrupt
cohort within the contemporary House of Commons to the bare minimum assortment
of states necessary to block an amendment under the formula described by the
proposed constitution was on its own merits fundamentally flawed. For one
thing, the Parliament of Great Britain was a body which met constantly – though
not perpetually – over the course of its term of existence between one election
and another. Legislation was considered, and read, and debated, and voted upon,
all of which provided the members sent from “rotten” constituencies any number
of opportunities to exert their influence over the business of government. The
tenth percentage of the American population of which Henry expressed his
especial dread represented a comparative abstraction. He was not referring to
ten percent of the membership of the House of Representatives, or ten percent
of the Senate, or ten percent of the state legislatures, or even ten percent of
the men elected to and seated therein. What he claimed to fear was rather that
ten percent of the total population of the United States of America whose elected
representatives in the state legislatures could defeat a proposed amendment to
the Constitution by withholding ratification. The figure itself, it bears
recalling, was not wrong. The delegates of one tenth of the American population
could in fact stymie the passage of an otherwise successful amendment. This was,
however, an exceptionally unlikely outcome given the arrangement of states
whose legislators would need to find common cause. It was also preconditioned
by the need for a proposed amendment to secure a two-thirds majority in both
houses of Congress. As this latter requirement represented, by design, a steep
hill for any proposal to surmount it was thus also quite unlikely on any given
day that the aforementioned alliance of state lawmakers would even be given the
chance to flex their obstructionist muscles.
Not only did Parliament, by comparison,
meet multiple times a year, every year, but that same body possessed far
greater constitutional authority than even its closest counterpart in the
proposed United States Congress. As mentioned above, alterations to the text of
the United States Constitution would need to pass through a complex – and
theoretically quite lengthy – process of approval before finally being implemented.
After first securing the agreement of either two-thirds of the House of
Representatives and the Senate or a simple majority of the state delegations in
a national convention called in response to the petition of two-thirds of the
state legislatures, the amendment in question would then require the further
ratification of three-fourths of the total number of state legislatures or of
three-fourths of the total number of conventions called by the same for the
purpose of ratification. In theory and in practice, the need to follow such procedures
introduced a great deal of delay into the process of altering the United States
Constitution and ensured that no one body or constituency could claim exclusive
control. Notwithstanding the 27th Amendment – a historical oddity,
being one of the first proposed and the last ratified – many of the successful
articles in question have experienced lengthy gestation periods between being
approved by Congress and validated by the states. The first parcel of ten
amendments, for example, collectively known as the Bill of Rights, received the
requisite congressional approval on September 25th, 1789 – seven
months into the first session of Congress – and was fully ratified over two
years later on December 15th, 1791. While other amendments have
enjoyed much shorter intervals between passage in Congress and ratification by
the states – the 26th claiming the briefest yet at a scant one
hundred days – many more clock in at over a year, or over two years, or even in
excess of three years. In consequence, amidst all of this time and all of these
procedures, it would seem fair to describe amendments to the proposed
constitution as both an uncommon occurrence and one whose accomplishment
entails a great many opportunities for second thoughts and careful scrutiny.
This is eminently not the case as regards
the British Constitution. Being an unwritten document – if such a thing can be
said to exist – the constitution of Great Britain essentially comprises every
law in force at a given moment within the legal confines of that selfsame
nation. The main pillars of the British Constitution are generally held to
include the Magna Carta (1215), the Petition of Right (1628), the Bill of
Rights (1689), and the Act of Union (1707), though in truth any piece of
legislation granted approval by Parliament – or indeed any court ruling which
determines how legislation is executed – can be said to form a part of the broader
constitutional framework. Whereas the United States Constitution represents a
singular, integral, codified text, the British Constitution thereby exists as
something more like a centuries-old accretion of acts, and rulings, and
principles from which the structure and authority of the British government is
customarily derived. This undeniably allows for a great deal of flexibility, there
being no formal limit upon what Parliament can or cannot do within its
particular sphere save whatever laws continue to be in force that it cannot
find the consensus to alter. At the same time, however, it also means that any
session of Parliament can alter the “Constitution” without special authority
and as rapidly as a majority can be assembled. If the Commons and the Lords
determined – after much debate, no doubt – to repeal the terms of the Bill of
Rights, for example, they could absolutely do so. It would be a terribly
foolish thing to attempt, the Bill having served for centuries as a guarantee
of Parliament’s independence against the interference of the Crown. All the
same, it would be entirely within their power to accomplish.
Bearing this fact in mind, the
approximately twenty percent of the membership of the House of Commons whose
seats, as of the turn of the 19th century, were owed directly to the
mechanism of political corruption inarguably possessed a far greater influence
over the character of the British Constitution than did their American
counterparts as described by Patrick Henry. Granting, of course, that this
selfsame cohort of MPs sent from the various rotten boroughs were unlikely to
share a common objective – and were thus unlikely to bring their full,
collective strength to bear upon or against a given initiative – their presence
as Members of Parliament placed them far closer to the reins of power than the
obstructionists that Henry attempted to identify. The latter being the various
state legislators who together represented one-tenth of the total population of
the American republic, their ability to exert any effect at all upon the
relevant constitutional status quo would be wholly contingent upon the passage
of amendments through the aforementioned first step of a codified two-step
procedure. And even in the event that a proposed amendment was successfully
submitted to the states – an outcome which, between 1789 and 1992, occurred on
average about once every thirteen years – the offending ten percent would be so
scattered among small and dissimilar states as to render a convergence of
opinion and action practically impossible. The rotten MPs, while similarly
unlikely to cooperate, would enjoy a great many more chances to do so and could
act far more directly upon the primary object in question. Henry’s claim,
therefore, that, “English liberty is, in this case, on a firmer foundation than
American liberty [,]” would appear to be wholly unfounded.
It
remains something of an open question whether Henry knew this to be the case or
not. As mentioned above, likely no one on Earth in 1788 could have spoken with
certainty as to the relative level and influence of corruption within the
contemporary British House of Commons. The relevant information simply hadn’t
been gathered, and indeed wouldn’t be for some forty years on. What was known,
however, as something of a truism on both sides of the Atlantic was that the
House of Commons as it then existed was very, very corrupt. People knew what a
rotten borough was, and that certain wealthy families essentially owned them,
and that the resulting seats in Parliament were little more than aristocratic possessions.
In Britain itself, suspicion of this arrangement and desire for reform most
certainly did exist as of the waning decades of the 18th century,
though it tended to remain confined to certain isolated factions within the
larger proto-party structure. In the United States, however, whose inhabitants
had but recently settled a successful war for independence from the authority
of Parliament and the Crown, belief in the corruption of the House of Commons
was doubtless much closer to being universal. Having just witnessed – and
suffered at the hands of – what to their eyes appeared to be a determined
impulse within Parliament towards unprincipled self-interest, the late 18th
century inhabitants of the United States of America had no particular reason to
believe that the House of Commons wasn’t tremendously, overwhelmingly,
irredeemably corrupt. Not only would this perception have afforded with their
understanding of why the events of the 1760s and 1770s transpired as they did –
Parliament having been taken over by a coterie of petty gentry and greedy
financiers – but it would also have served to buttress their emerging national
self-image. Whereas everybody knew that Great Britain was plagued by endemic
corruption, they could conceivably begin to tell themselves, the United States
was possessed of a political culture that prized liberty, integrity, and
justice above all else.
Herein Patrick Henry’s rhetorical genius
was able to spring into action. If everybody “knew” that the House of Commons
was horrendously corrupt despite a complete absence of solid data as to the
nature and extent of the problem, it was possible in the course of a given
debate to say just about anything that was generally consistent with the theme
thereof without fear of being called into question. Parliamentary corruption
could thus fairly be said to exist, within the context of late 18th
century American political discourse, as a fixed point of knowledge. It was a cliché,
a maxim, a piece of received wisdom; its validity was taken almost entirely for
granted in spite of there being little in the way of hard data to back it up. Depending
on the nature of the debate and its participants, of course, someone might
conceivably call into question the extent to which such claims were really
true. But just as its proponents couldn’t rigorously support the claim, neither
could its detractors offer much evidence to the contrary. For the purposes of
Patrick Henry – whose aim, again, was to convince his fellow delegates to the
Virginia Ratifying Convention that the proposed constitution was too dangerous
to be adopted – this vague but immutable sense of validity was arguably the
key. If every member of his audience believed or had heard tell that the
British House of Commons was notoriously corrupt and none of them could prove
conclusively that this wasn’t the case, then what might be the effect of
asserting that this selfsame House of Commons in fact offered greater security
to the liberties of the British people than did the proposed constitution to
those of their American counterparts? What counter might Henry’s opponents
possibly have offered?
Doubtless their first instinct would have
been to affirm that the proposed constitution was not near so poorly designed
as to permit the kind of lopsided distribution of authority for which the
contemporary House of Commons had in America become notorious. There could be
no comparison, they might fairly have claimed, between the unlikeliest outcome
of the amending formula and the effects of the everyday corruption implied by
the very existence of the rotten boroughs, and it was plainly disingenuous to
suggest otherwise. Sound though this argument would have been, however, it had
also yet to be proven or disproven. Likely the supporters of the proposed
constitution were right and the scenario that Henry forecasted was so
improbable as to be practically meaningless. But, then again, perhaps Henry was
right and the ability of so small a proportion of the population to stymie the
passage of potentially needful amendments would in time spell the downfall of
liberty in the American republic. Only time, as it were, would tell for
certain. Casting about for alternative arguments, Henry’s opponents would
likely have been at a loss to lay hands on anything more solid.
They might have attempted to affirm that the
House of Commons was not as corrupt as all that, the purpose of which would
have been to thereby insinuate that the proposed constitution was more secure
than Henry had described. Having to push against the overwhelming weight of
popular opinion would have made this an especially undesirable approach,
however, and one which the aforementioned paucity of hard data would have
rendered yet more difficult in turn. Supporters of the proposed constitution
might also have avowed that the House of Commons was in fact far more corrupt
than Henry indicated and that the peculiarities of the amending formula – while
indeed problematic in theory – were in practice much less likely to obstruct
the realization of the general public good than was the persistent ability of a
moneyed few to buy and sell seats in Parliament. While this would surely have
embodied a more outwardly favorable approach, it would also have run up against
the aforementioned absence of verifiable information. How, in short, could one
determine in 1788 precisely the degree to which the House of Commons was
corrupt? All that Henry had said was, “We have heard that there is a great deal
of bribery practiced in the House of Commons, in England, and that many of the
members raise themselves to preferments by selling the rights of the whole of
the people.” In order to convincingly argue that this represented an
understatement of fact, one would have ideally had to bring to bear such
definite figures as would render the question wholly unequivocal. It would not
do to simply say, “Actually, things are much worse.” Rather, one ought to have
explained how much worse and by what means. Since this would have proven next
to impossible to accomplish – absent the time and resources necessary to
complete an exhaustive survey of the rotten boroughs and the effects of their
influence – this counterargument to Henry’s decidedly vague assertion would
likewise have availed his opponents of little advantage.
Perhaps the most accurate response to
Henry’s claim would have been to agree in principle that the contemporary House
of Commons was very corrupt and that the amending formula described by the
proposed constitution was not without its flaws while also pointedly affirming
that these two truths bore little if any relation to one another. The
corruption represented by the existence of the rotten boroughs stemmed from a
general resistance within contemporary British political culture to
institutional reform and to the expansion of the electoral franchise. The
deficiencies of the amending formula – including its theoretical vulnerability
to minority control – were conversely the unintended but perhaps inevitable
consequences of attempting to describe a practical system of constitutional
modification which struck a balance between stability and openness. Both of
these embodied potential problems for the respective political frameworks of
which they were a part. But they were problems of a fundamentally different
nature; comparing them directly could yield but little of philosophical value.
For one of Henry’s opponents in the
Virginia Ratifying Convention to have attempted to affirm this point, however,
would arguably have been to commit an even worse tactical blunder than embodied
by the first two approaches here described. Admitting that either of the points
which Henry had attempted to make was in any sense true would have been
tantamount, rhetorically, to admitting defeat. By the terms of debate which the
former Governor of Virginia had set out, the only options available to his
audience were either to agree with his assertions or deny them outright. There
could be no quibbling about details, no pointing to specifics, for neither
would have helped to avoid the trap that Henry had set. Speaking just enough
truth to maneuver his opponents into admitting that he was in some capacity
correct, he could then swiftly claim victory and dismiss all else that was
said. Harnessing popular opinion – by, for example, trying an argument against
the proposed constitution to the common perception of corruption within the
British House of Commons – made this kind of tactic yet easier to deploy.
Such was the admitted genius – one might
even fairly say the deviousness – of Patrick Henry within the realm of public
debate. It didn’t matter, under the rules he had set for himself, that he
tended to make gross generalizations, or treat assumption as though they were
facts, or practice a “winner take all” style of argument wherein complexity had
no place. So long as he could claim to have won – by forcing his opponents to
grant any part of his premise or to wrestle their way out of the logical
frameworks he had constructed – the actual substance of his arguments mattered
very little. What did matter were the things for which Henry claimed to stand.
As he made clear quite often over the course of his oration before the
assembled delegates of the Virginia Ratifying Convention, he was a firm
believer in the absolute sovereignty of the American states. He believed in
American liberty first, and the American Union second. He thought it paramount
that the American people refuse to acquiesce to any form of government that did
not explicitly recognize their fundamental natural rights. And he held it to be
an absolute truth that human beings simply weren’t built to voluntarily relinquish
whatever power came into their possession. It was wholly inconsequential that
almost none of the arguments which Henry offered alongside these principles in
any way served as proof of their essential validity. The important thing was
that Henry consistently “beat” his opponents. If he was right, and he believed
“x,” “y,” and “z,” then it followed by a kind of transitive property that “x,”
“y,” and “z” must also be right. Logically, of course, this kind of equation is
exceedingly specious. Nevertheless, it makes perfect rhetorical sense, and
Patrick Henry was nothing if not an undisputed master of the rhetorical
arts.
No comments:
Post a Comment