The justice – or rather injustice –
of the burgeoning conflict between Great Britain and the Thirteen Colonies
having been well and fully established over the course of Part II, Section III
of his Observations, Richard Price
next proceeded to discuss in Section IV the extent to which he believed that
the honor of the British state and people were particularly entangled with the
outcome of said struggle. The resulting examination, presented under the title
“Of the Honour of the Nation, as affected by the War with America [,]” though adopting a rather broad view of the subject at
hand, nevertheless managed to frame the position and actions of the
contemporary British government with a remarkable degree of moral clarity and
rhetorical force. History was Price’s medium of choice, both recent and
ancient, and his aim was to translate the shame and odium his countrymen might
have been given to feel about a specific incident from the past into a clearer
understanding of what their own government was attempting in the present. In so
doing, the author of Observations
effectively demonstrated the consistency of some of his most loudly-voiced
convictions, his continued ambivalence – if not outright disdain – towards the
moral character of classical antiquity, and his urgent belief that the events
then transpiring in distant America embodied ill portents for the people of
Britain proper.
As with previous sections of Observations, Section IV began with
Price’s citation of the particular claim he intended to refute. Specifically,
it was that which purported, on behalf of the sitting government, “That our
honor is engaged; and that we cannot recede without the most humiliating
concessions.” Price’s first point in opposition to this stance was a relatively
simple one, though by his own admission he rather regretted the fact of it. “A
distinction should be made [,]” he avowed,
Between the
nation and its rulers. It is melancholy that there should be ever any reason
for making such a distinction. A government is, or ought to be, nothing but an
institution for collecting and carrying into execution the will of the people.
But so far is this from being in general the fact, that the measures of
government, and the sense of the people, are sometimes in direct opposition to
one another; nor does it often happen
that any certain conclusion can be drawn
from the one to the other.
Perhaps the most
striking element of this passage is the evident gulf it described between the
optimism with which Price envisioned government and the sense of mistrust with
which he observed it. Granted, previous sections of his Observations attested quite powerfully to his believe that the
institutions of the contemporary British state no longer served to accurately
represent the interests of the general population. He had also already made it
substantially clear that he perceived the British ministerial elite as being
almost wholly in thrall to a coterie of bankers, financiers, and merchants
whose overriding commercial interests where largely at odds with those of the
British people as a whole.
To some extent,
however, these specific criticisms constituted mere sideswipes at a much larger issue.
Describing Parliament as unrepresentative and government as corrupt was, after
all, something less than stating plainly and simply that the British state and
the British people had become separate to the point of working at cross
purposes. Corruption and a lack of representation in government were most
definitely serious causes of dysfunction to which Price was justifiably
motivated to seek some form of remedy. But a state of affairs in which the
people wanted fundamentally different – even opposing – things than their
government could fairly be characterized as a full-blown disorder. Price’s
admission that, “The measures of government, and the sense of the people, are
sometimes in direct opposition to one another” could therefore be said to
constitute his gravest evaluation yet of the health and wellbeing of
contemporary British civilization. After all, a government that works directly
against the wishes of its constituents essentially constitutes a rejection of
the very definition of government itself. It is not merely dysfunctional, but
broken. It does not simply function badly, but rather ceases to function at
all.
Interestingly
enough, though Price was speaking from within the context of late 1770s Britain
– a time and place freighted with any number of very specific issues and
influences – exactly this kind of sentiment became a staple of mainstream
American political discourse beginning in the middle 1790s. Driven to
increasingly virulent factionalism by the pressures exerted on the nation’s yet
nascent political culture during the tumultuous post-war years and the debates
which accompanied the ratification of the United States Constitution, Americans
entered the last decade of the 18th century arguably more disunited
politically than they had been since the first stirrings of the Revolution in
the middle 1760s. And while formal political parties were slow to form –
consequent to widespread opposition to the concept – the ideological cleavages
which would come to define the next several decades of American political life
were very much in evidence. Generally speaking, these divisions resolved
themselves around two basic philosophical poles, being advocacy for a powerful
central government and support for powerful state governments, respectively.
The former, falling under the label of Federalism, argued for the creation of
national means to address national priorities – from debt, to infrastructure,
to the military, to trade – and tended to find its strongest supporter among
merchants, financiers, manufacturers, and soldiers. The latter position,
adopting the equally vague title of Republicanism, meanwhile conversely
advocated for political decentralization as a means of preserving civil
liberties, championed policies like easy access to credit and free trade, and
was most popular among Southern plantation owners, yeoman farmers, and urban
tradesmen.
It ought to come
as no surprise that it was the Republican faction – or Republican Party, or
Democratic-Republicans – whose leaders and scribes very soon found cause to
echo many of the sentiments expressed by the likes of Richard Price in their
attempts to describe the dangers they perceived in the governments of President
George Washington (1732-1799) and President John Adams (1735-1826). The
Federalists who then held the reins of power – led though most of this period
by Alexander Hamilton (1755-1804) – were variously accused by opposition
Republicans of being pseudo-monarchists, slavish Anglophiles, tyrants-in-waiting,
and corrupt aristocrats whose financial interests and lust for power had long
since overpowered whatever conviction they might once had held to preserve the
liberties of their fellow Americans. Republican faction leader Thomas Jefferson
(1743-1826) captured the extent to which he believed this served to separate
the Federalists in power from their nominal constituents in a 1798 letter to
fellow Virginian John Taylor (1753-1824), stating that,
The body of
our countrymen is substantially republican through every part of the Union. It
was the irresistible influence & popularity of Gen Washington, played off
by the cunning of Hamilton, which turned the government over to anti-republican
hands, or turned the republican members, chosen by the people, into
anti-republicans.
Note the dichotomy
that this description presents. The people, Jefferson affirmed, were naturally
republican, while the government, by way of influence and cunning, was
anti-republican. The difference being inherently artificial and contrived, the
natural state of government in America – and thus the natural connection
between the people and their administrators – had thus by definition been
disrupted.
A more specific – and arguably more
significant – example of this same characterization can be found in the public
criticisms Jefferson offered to certain Adams Administration policies in the
so-called Kentucky Resolutions. Alarmed by the passage and implementation of
the Alien and Sedition Acts (1798), Jefferson – then serving as Vice-President
under Adams – anonymously penned a series of condemnations that were
subsequently ratified and published by the Kentucky state legislature. The
general thrust of these remonstrances was that the relevant statutes appeared
to place the national government above the authority of either the Constitution
or the American people. Under their terms, Jefferson explained,
The general
government may place any act they think proper on the list of crimes, and punish
it themselves, whether enumerated or not enumerated by the Constitution as
cognizable by them […] they may transfer its cognizance to the President […]
who may himself be the accuser, counsel, judge, and jury, whose suspicions may
be the evidence, his order the sentence, his officer the executioner, and his
breast the sole record of the transaction […] And the barriers of the
Constitution thus swept from us all, no rampart now remains against the
passions and the power of a majority of Congress, to protect from a like
exportation, or other grievous punishment, the minority of the same body, the
legislatures, judges, governors, and counsellors of the states, nor their other
peaceable inhabitants, who may venture to reclaim the constitutional rights and
liberties of the states and people [.]
Of particular note
in this passage is Jefferson’s identification of the President and Congress
alike as shared source of distress, as well as his evident belief in the
efficacy of the Constitution. It was not the very notion of a national
government that the leader of the Republican faction feared, it seemed – though
his other writings would show that he certainly harbored concerns – but rather
the way that said government was used.
The “barriers of
the Constitution” and its various enumerated powers were unfortunately only as
dependable as the parties involved desired them to be. That the Federalists in
Congress and in the cabinet of President Adams had, by Jefferson’s reckoning,
chosen to ignore these essential protections in service of their own partisan
pursuits thus formed the core of his criticism. Like the North Ministry – whom
many of its members had ironically risked their lives to oppose in the 1770s
and 1780s – the contemporary Federalist establishment embodied to Jefferson and
his Republican cohorts a thing apart from the people whose interests they
claimed to represent. The general population, he affirmed in his aforementioned
letter to John Taylor, were “substantially republican” while the government was
somehow in the hands of “anti-republicans.” The people had chosen to ratify a
Constitution blessed with numerous checks upon the abuse of legislative or
executive power – ranging from prohibitions against concentrations of authority
to protections of due process – while the Adams Administration had seemingly
made it possible for the President to act in certain matters of criminal
justice as, “The accuser, counsel, judge, and jury,” and left
vulnerable, “The minority of [Congress], the
legislatures, judges, governors, and counsellors of the states, [and] their
other peaceable inhabitants [.]”
One could arguably
come no closer than this to the criticism Richard Price had leveled at his own
government two decades earlier. For that matter, the further similarities
between Price’s condemnations of contemporary British society and the standard
Republican appraisal of the culture of government and business fostered by
their Federalist opponents – i.e. a denunciation of excessive wealth and
corruption, advocacy for political de-centralization, etc. – would seem to
affirm the existence of a strong ideological connection between the
pre-Revolutionary Old Whig reformism of dissident British intellectuals and
statesmen like Richard Price and the post-Revolutionary agrarian populism of
opposition figures like Thomas Jefferson. And though the question of whether
this connection was direct or indirect – conscious or unconscious – is almost
certainly too involved to delve into here, the possibility nevertheless bears
acknowledging that some of the core tenets of Jeffersonian Republicanism may
have been as much a product of and development from earlier trends in British
political culture and public discourse as Hamiltonian Federalism, American
Constitutionalism, or the very impulse to resistance that sparked the American
Revolution.
All that being having said, the
subject at hand once more demands attention. Price, though evidently keen to
point out very early in Part II, Section IV of his Observations that the British government and the British people
were not necessarily of like minds in all things – and that he furthermore
wasn’t certain whether a dishonor suffered by said government would necessarily
reflect at all upon the integrity of its constituents – nevertheless seemed
quite willing to put this same assertion aside when examining the fundamental
moral implications of the North Ministry’s campaign to quell the ongoing
rebellion in British America. Whether the British people generally agreed with
Lord North or not was evidently of little consequence in this particular
context. In either case, Price avowed, “The disgrace to which a kingdom must
submit by making concessions, is nothing to that of being the aggressors in an
unrighteous quarrel; and dignity, in such circumstances, consists in retracting
freely, speedily, and magnanimously.” This declaration, like so many of Price’s
condemnations of the North Ministry’s conduct, served to deconstruct the
orthodox British government position by essentially turning it on its head.
To the argument that the nation’s honor had become so wholly tied to the successful pacification of
America that no retreat was thought possible without suffering disgrace, Price
accordingly countered that there could be no honor in the victory then being
pursued. The British cause was fundamentally unjust, the war a wholly
unnecessary conflict between members of the same imperial family, and honor
could only be salvaged – not won, but salvaged – if wrong was admitted and
magnanimity freely offered. Seeking perhaps to place a final emphasis on the
validity of this position, Price then proceeded to offer a quote from William
Pitt (1708-1778), Whig statesman, staunch opponent of institutional corruption,
and noted friend of the American colonies. “RECTITUDE IS DIGNITY [,]” Price
cited the former Prime Minister as having said, “OPPRESSION ONLY IS MEANNESS;
AND JUSTICE, HONOR.” Having failed to abide by this maxim, the North Ministry
and its supporters could make no claim to the possession of honor in their
pursuit of victory in colonial America.
No comments:
Post a Comment