The rationale that Richard Price next
sought to examine and deconstruct in the text of his Observations for the continued submission of the American colonies
to the British government was somewhat more figurative than those he had
theretofore addressed. Whereas the claims he had investigated up to that point
sought to invoke – albeit somewhat vaguely – the facts and figures that set
America and Britain apart, this next assertion attempted to substitute allegory
for even the appearance of logic. “But we are the PARENT STATE,” Price quoted certain
of his countrymen as having declared, as if that phrase obliterated all doubt
as to proper roles to be assayed by Britain and America, respectively. The
author of Observations would have
none of this, of course, and proceeded to dismantle the “parent state” argument
in both its literal and figurative sense.
By claiming for Great Britain the title of
parent to America’s presumed role as child, the advocates of British supremacy
that Price was evidently citing were doubtless attempting to imply that the
American colonies owed their origin to Britain, that they had enjoyed British
guidance and support in the formative years of their existence, and that they
consequently owed the British government some degree of deference and fealty. It
would be difficult to say to what extent this hypothetical obligation extended,
though the context would seem to imply an indefinite degree of submission over
an indefinite period of time. Understandably – given his aforementioned
understanding of the nature and significance of sovereignty – this was not a state
of affairs to which Price could comfortably resign himself. For one thing, it
seemed to him that the implications of the doctrine – if taken to their logical
conclusion – extended beyond just the relationship between Britain and America.
“The English came from Germany [,]”
Price thus pointedly observed. “Does this give the German states a right to tax us?”
In point of fact, England had indeed been
settled between approximately the 5th and 7th centuries
by an assortment of Germanic tribes – among them, most famously, the Angles and
the Saxons. These various continental peoples migrated into what was then
post-Roman Britannia, either as invaders or by the invitation of its native
Celtic inhabitants, and proceeded to completely transform the cultural and
political makeup of the region by about the end of the 9th century. This
would not be the last time England would be invaded and settled on a large
scale by an otherwise foreign people – the Norman conquest of 1066 having
further redefined both the nature of English culture and its relationship to
continental Europe – but it arguably represented the single most significant
event by which a former province of the Roman Empire became a distinct socio-political
entity.
The purpose of Price’s question, therefore,
was to draw a comparison between the settlement of America by various
communities of English/British migrants over the course of the 17th
and 18th centuries and the settlement of Britain by the Angles and
Saxons over a millennium previous. Specifically, it was the implication of the
“parent state” claim – i.e. that being the nominal originators of the American
colonies gave Britain a claim to their continued obedience – that was being
called to examination. If, Price was essentially asking, America ought
continually to defer to Britain, submit to the authority of its government, and
pay whatever taxes the legislature thereof assessed simply because the
colonists and their ancestors originally came from Britain, did it not then
follow that Britain should similarly submit itself to the governments then
administering the lands from which their own ancestors migrated? This was, of
course, a fairly ridiculous proposition. Not only were there far too many
sovereign or semi-sovereign states then in existence in what is now Germany for
it to be at all clear which one Britain owed its fealty, but a number of them
were in fact its rivals for influence in the ongoing contest for regional
dominance. Therein, however, lay the rhetorical strength of Price’s approach. Just
as Benjamin Franklin had earlier satirized the “parent state” concept by
writing a declaration ostensibly on behalf of the King of Prussia claiming his
right to mastery over Britain – An Edict by
the King of Prussia, publish September 22nd, 1773 – Price was
using the plainly evident illogic of one situation to expose the same quality
in another.
Britain naturally had no reason to
surrender its sovereignty to the Prussian government, or indeed to any
government of any German state, and was under no legal obligation to do so.
Granted, the ancestors of the contemporary English people had originally
migrated from lands now falling within one or more of these states, but a great
deal – on the order of one thousand years of history – had transpired since
then. To expect Parliament to give way to some foreign sovereign simply because
that sovereign ruled over the ancestral homeland of Parliament’s ancient forefathers
was therefore plainly absurd. And while it perhaps also warrants
acknowledgement that far less time had passed between the settlement of British
America between the 1610s and 1730s and the emergence of the Anglo-American
crisis in the 1760s and 1770s, the principle which Price was evidently endeavoring
to expose still applied. At some point between the time that Germanic peoples
set foot in England in the 400s and the establishment of the first Anglo-Saxon
kingdom in the 500s, some threshold had been crossed whereby the relevant
migrant peoples and their descendants were no longer bound by whatever tribal
authority they had recognized in their native Germany. Impossible though it may
be to pinpoint when and how this occurred, clearly it did occur. In
consequence, it may fairly be inferred that the same shift was bound to take
place within the Anglo-American relationship.
At some point, for some reason, the
American colonies would reach a stage in their development after which they
would no longer be required to acknowledge the authority of their British
forebears. Either that, or Britain was in fact still bound to obey the dictates
of the German authorities that the ancestors of its citizens had long since
left behind. Doubtless neither of these eventualities would have seemed
particularly desirable to those among Price’s countrymen who continued to
insist that American owed its allegiance to Britain, but that was most
certainly the point. Either nations were the prime source of sovereignty, or
people were. Either a person could define their own citizenship, or they – and
their children, and their children’s children – were bound for all time to the
authority under which they were born. British history certainly seemed to bear
out the truth of the former. When the ancient Angles and Saxons migrated to
sub-Roman Britannia, they did not thereby extend the authority of the Germanic
chieftains whose authority they had previously been given to acknowledge.
Rather, they formed a series of unique polities – Kent, Mercia, Northumbria,
etc. – wholly outside the sovereignty of their homelands and possessed of
governments of their own derivation and authority.
Just so, Price seemed to indicate, the
original settlers of the Thirteen Colonies had left the authority of Parliament
behind when they departed from British ports and set sail for America. Granted,
most of the relevant colonial ventures were conducted under the auspices of
royal charters. And it also bears acknowledging that the resulting colonial
governments did tend to acknowledge the authority of Parliament in certain
matters of policy. These were, however, often described by the colonists
themselves as essentially voluntary measures. Rather than pay homage to the
reigning British monarch out of obligation – which their forefathers had been
made to do while still residing in Britain proper – they did so out of a sense
of tradition and fellow-feeling. Rather than bow to the authority of Parliament
in recognition of the domestic supremacy thereof, they gave way to the dictates
of the British legislature only as pragmatism and courtesy deemed necessary.
Far from being dispatched by their government with express instructions to
establish the authority thereof in North America, these migrants – among them
religious dissenters, debtors, criminals, and utopians – had left of their own
accord, in large part at their own expense, and proceeded to build communities
for themselves that suited their needs and conformed to their respective
visions of socio-political harmony. The reigning British government in 1776 could
accordingly no better claim them than indeed the Elector of Saxony could
realistically demand that the descendants of his ancient subjects in Britain
render unto him the homage he was due. The settlements of Britain and America
were neither of them wholly state-directed affairs, and the resulting
communities were accordingly responsible for determining to whom – if anyone –
their fealty was owed and to what end – if any – their sovereign efforts were
directed.
Even, however, if one were to indulge the
notion of Britain as the “parent state” of the American colonies – with the
former explicitly guiding and supporting the efforts and development of the
latter – Price maintained that the colonists were yet still in the right to
find fault with the manner in which they had theretofore been treated. “Children,”
he thus affirmed in Part II, Section I of Observations,
“Having no property, and being incapable of guiding themselves, the author of
nature has committed the care of them to their parents, and subjected them to
their absolute authority.” Nothing could be more natural or more obvious. At
the same time, Price continued, “There is [also] a period when, having acquired
property, and a capacity of judging for themselves, [children] become
independent agents; and when, for this reason, the authority of theirs parents
ceases, and becomes nothing but the respect and influence due to benefactors.” This,
too, was an eminently logical outcome of the parent/child dynamic. At some
point, every child who survives infancy becomes an adult, takes full
responsibility for themselves and their actions, and enters the world on equal
standing with that enjoyed by their parents. Affection (ideally) still remains
between parents and child, along with, as Price acknowledged, some degree of
respect and trust built upon years of successful and loving guidance. But the
adult offspring ought not to feel bound by the dictates of their parent as they
did when still a child. Having come into their own, they alone must determine
in all things the proper course of action. Just so, the loving parent should
openly welcome this day, as they themselves were guided to it by their own
progenitors, and encourage their children to embrace the independence for which
they have been prepared.
Applying this same logic to the
relationship between the Thirteen Colonies and Great Britain, however – in
light of the aforementioned characterizations of Britain as the “parent state”
of the colonies – produced a somewhat less rosy outcome. Whereas, Price
explained, successive British governments should accordingly have been
lessening the extent to which Parliament exerted its authority over the
colonies in anticipation of the day when they became wholly independent states,
quite the opposite had been allowed to transpire. “Like mad parents,” Price
asserted, “At the very time when out authority should have been most relaxed,
we have carried it to the greatest extent, and exercised it with the greatest
rigour.” Not only did this course of action – i.e. taxing residents of the
colonies without their consent, garrisoning troops among them, restricting
their commerce, abrogating their governments, etc. – represent an injustice in
itself for the flagrant manner in which it violated the civil rights of the
effected colonist, but it directly contradicted the notion that Britain ought
to have been regarded as though it was the parent of the Thirteen Colonies.
Having established themselves upon a firm basis of government, affirmed the
rule of law within their borders, and taken to sustaining themselves via a
robust commercial intercourse with Britain proper, the colonies of British
America were clearly no longer in need of the kind of guidance and discipline
that a child requires. It should therefore have followed that the colonies
could not be considered children any longer, and that the government of Great
Britain was obligated to release its accustomed hold upon American affairs and
allow the inhabitant thereof to chart whatever course they desired. If this was
not the case, of course – that is to say, if Britain refused to acknowledge
that the time had passed when its authority was any longer required in America
– then perhaps the colonies were not children, Britain was not their parent,
and the entirely argument was well and truly moot.
Such blatant inconsistencies between
rhetoric and action were very much at the core of Price’s subsequent
complaints. Proceeding in Part II, Section I of his Observations to interrogate the various explanations he had
encountered in favor of Britain’s continued mastery over the American colonies,
he thus hit upon – and wholly eviscerated – the question of financial
investment. “But we have, it is said, protected them,” Price wrote, “And run
deeply in debt on their account.” Vague though this claim may be, the thrust of
it would seem obvious enough. From the beginning of the English colonial
project in the late 16th century to what was then the present day of
the late 1770s, successive British governments had indeed spent a cumulatively
impressive sum protecting and helping to expand the various settlements of
British America. The British Navy had protected colonial shipping and ensured
that American harbors were safe from foreign depredations, the British Army had
lent invaluable assistance to local militias in holding back both indigenous
threats and the aggressive ventures of rival European powers, and British
negotiators had signed treaty after treaty with neighboring native peoples,
thus greatly expanding the available territory into which it was possible to
migrate. The benefits of these measures to the inhabitants of British America
were exceedingly substantial, not at all unlike the cost of the same to the
contemporary British Treasury. The Seven Years War (1754-1763), while bringing
about the final elimination of France from the North American colonial contest,
proved to be a particularly expensive endeavor, having exploded the British
national debt from £75,000,000 before the war to £130,000,000 by the beginning
of 1764. Bearing this all in mind, it would thus seem quite fair to grant that
Great Britain had indeed invested a great deal in the continued prosperity of
its American dependencies, to the point of taking on theretofore unimaginable
financial obligations.
Richard Price did not claim otherwise. The
degree to which successive British governments confirmed their interest in the
American colonial project via repeated financial commitments was doubtless as
plain to him as to any modern observer. He did, however, question the rationale
behind these repeated investments. “Will anyone say,” he thereby asked of his
countrymen, “That all we have done for them has not been more on our own account, than on theirs?” It would seem a rather obvious
line of inquiry – that is to say, it might fairly be taken as a given that
Britain did not act as it did out of pure altruism. To those among his
countrymen who were so capable of deluding themselves as to imagine that
Britain’s interest in the American colonial project was wholly selfless and
compassionate in nature, however, Price was endeavoring to illustrate the
various benefits America provided to its supposed European benefactor. “Have
they not helped us to pay our taxes,” he asked,
To support
our poor, and to bear the burden of our debts, by taking from us, at our own
price, all the commodities with which we can supply them?–Have they not, for
our advantage, submitted to many restraints in acquiring property? […] Has not
their exclusive trade with us been for many years one of the chief sources of
our national wealth and power? […] In the last war particularly, it is well
know, that they ran themselves deeply in debt; and that the parliament thought
is necessary to grant them considerable sums annually as compensations for
going beyond their abilities in assisting us. And in this course would they
have continued for many future years; perhaps for ever.–In short, were an
accurate account stated, it is by no means certain which side would appear to
be most indebted.
These were
significant claims on Price’s part, to be certain. Indeed, it would have been
difficult to conclusively confirm or deny them without fairly intimate access
to any number of public and private accounts. That being said, the conclusion
which followed was almost certainly an apt one. At its heart – and despite
appearances to the contrary – the Anglo-American relationship was essentially a
reciprocal one.
This should not be taken to mean
that it was also an entirely equitable association, of course. The core
principle of mercantilism – then the guiding economic philosophy of most every
major European power – was that there was a finite amount of wealth in the
world, and that it was the purpose of trade, and taxation, and war, and just
about every other power possessed by government to ensure that the largest sum
of resources possible was collected and concentrated in the coffers of the
nation. It would therefore not have made sense philosophically for Britain to
engage in anything like a fair and unstructured commercial intercourse with its
various American dependencies. Indeed, from the perspective of Britain itself
the colonies existed almost entirely for the purpose of harvesting, processing,
and exporting the natural resources of the American continent and turning its
own output of manufactured goods into valuable hard currency. Price had rightly
pointed out as much in the passage cited above, and it would have been
difficult indeed for any but the most obtuse of his countrymen to deny that the
advantages they and their government had thereby accrued were sizeable indeed.
And while the inhabitants of the colonies were not blessed in return with
economic opportunities equal to those enjoyed by their British counterparts –
their trade, manufacturing, financial policy, and even physical movement were
all subject to restriction by British law – they at least received the benefit
of the aforementioned military and diplomatic assistance.
The point that Price was attempting
to make in the quoted section of his Observations
would thus seem to stand very much as he intended it. Within the context of the
Anglo-American relationship, Britain and the relevant colonies were certainly
not equals in terms of the privileges they enjoyed and the benefits they
derived. But nor could it be honestly stated that either rendered up an
advantage to the other without receiving something very valuable in return.
Britain, in exchange for admittedly extensive military and financial aid,
gained in America an exclusive source of raw materials like timber and produce,
as well as sole access to an expanding market for its yearly increasing output
of manufactured goods. At the same time, by allowing certain aspects of its
economy to be restricted via taxes and regulations in whose formulation it had
no part, America enjoyed the largely unquestioning protection of one of the
most powerful nations on the planet and access to a voracious market for its
own output of natural resources. Certainly it wasn’t a perfect arrangement.
Doubtless the British government would have preferred to spend far less money
defending colonial interests while also avoiding having to so frequently
wrangle with willful colonial governments. Just so, the American colonists
would surely rather have enjoyed access to British markets and manufactures
without having to submit to the accompanying economic regulations. At the very
least, however, it was a functional relationship, and one in which most costs
were clearly accompanied by corresponding benefits. While it might narrowly
have been conceivable to craft something better in its stead, it would have
been all too easy to replace it with something worse.