Before concluding this essay series on Federalist No. 78, it
remains to explore just a few more points of discussion. While these
forthcoming topics don’t necessarily fit into any of the themes that have been
covered thus far – context, pragmatism, or precedent – they are, I feel, too
interesting or too significant to simply gloss over. As a result – and as ever
I beg the indulgence of my dear, precious readers – what comes next will most
definitely lack the structural consistency which I flatter myself in thinking
that I normally maintain. Call this section a “one more thing” if you like.
Indeed, perhaps I should have.
Anyway, let’s get on with it.
At a point around the middle of No. 78 – in paragraphs ten,
eleven, and twelve, to be exact – Hamilton deployed a justification for
subordinating Congress to the terms of the proposed constitution which in
itself potentially reveals an attempt on his part to provide ideological
justification for a distinctly strategic choice made by the Framers. What in
God’s name is that supposed to mean, I hear you ask? Well, before I fully
explain, I ask you to please consider the following. In the first instance
(paragraph ten), Hamilton argued that to deny the superiority of the
Constitution to a mere Act of Congress would in effect affirm, “That the
Representatives of the People are superior to the People themselves [.]” In the
second (paragraph eleven), he declared that in all cases, “The Constitution
ought to be preferred to the statute; the intention of the People to the
intention of their agents.” And in the third (paragraph twelve) he affirmed,
“That where the will of the Legislature, declared in its statutes, stands in
opposition to that of the People, declared in the Constitution, the Judges
ought to be governed by the latter rather than the former.” In each of these
cases, it should be noted, Hamilton clearly sought to establish a strong rhetorical
relationship between the proposed constitution and “the People” of the United
States of America. At the same time, he also seemed intent on erecting a kind
of conceptual barrier between the general population and their representatives
in Congress. A given congressional statute, Hamilton seemed willing to admit,
could fairly be said to embody the aggregate will of “the People” at a
particular moment in time, but not in the same way that he seemed determined to
ascribe to the Constitution.
In short, this position boils down to the perception of a
difference in quality or legitimacy between everyday laws that are passed by
men chosen by their constituents for that purpose and a superseding fundamental
law that was approved by the voters themselves. The act of delegation inherent
in allowing Representatives and Senators to draft and approve laws in the place
of their constituents, by Hamilton’s evident reckoning, made all the
difference. Figuratively speaking, the hands of “the People” had touched the supreme
governing document – i.e. the Constitution – in a way that could not be said of
an act of Congress. This proximity lent greater legitimacy – not unlike rules
of inheritance that prioritize closeness of relation to a shared ancestor – and
thus made the Constitution the legally superior authority. In deference to
Hamilton, it was almost certainly a very wise choice on his part to pursue this
particular line of argument. “The People,” in the context of the American
Revolution and its immediate aftermath, was an exceptionally powerful
socio-political concept. As the sole inalienable source of authority in both
the British parliamentary and 18th century republican models of
government, the explicit will of the general population could theoretically
authorize or reject any action, and erect or tear down any administrative
institution. By unambiguously harnessing “the People” to the proposed
Constitution, therefore, Hamilton made it that much harder for his opponents to
decry those aspects of the document with which they found fault. No one could
claim, however valid or well-reasoned their complaints, that their particular
sense of discretion was superior to the will of “the People,” and the
Constitution was that embodied.
Sort of…
As with so many topics that have been discussed over the
course of this series, the gloss that Hamilton put on the relationship between
the American people and the Constitution – a characterization upon which he
based no small portion of his argument in Federalist No. 78 – was more complicated
than he made it seem. Recall, for instance, that in spite of Hamilton’s
insistence that the will of “the People” was “declared in the Constitution,”
the document itself was in fact drafted by a relatively small number of
delegates (fifty-five) dispatched to Philadelphia from twelve of the thirteen
extant states. Some, like Pennsylvania or Virginia, sent fairly large
contingents – eight and seven, respectively – while others like New Hampshire
(two) and New York (three) were comparatively underrepresented. It is also
worth noting that none of these selfsame delegates were elected by the general
population of their state – rather, they were selected and commissioned by the
legislatures of the same. Consider, as well, that none of the states submitted
the proposed constitution for public consideration in the form of a popular
referendum. Instead, in keeping with the Framers’ express recommendation, the
document was considered and adopted by delegates elected to a series of state
conventions called specifically for that purpose. As with the delegations
originally sent to Philadelphia, some of these state conventions were fairly
small – Delaware, for example, elected only thirty men to the task, while
Georgia sufficed with twenty-six – while others were substantially larger – the
people of South Carolina elected two hundred and seventy-one delegates, but
still less than the three hundred and fifty-five of Massachusetts – than the
existing Continental Congress.
Taking these facts in hand, Hamilton’s assertion that the
fully-ratified and accepted Constitution would in effect represent the express
will of the American people would seem to be something of an oversimplification.
On the basis of distance from “the hand of the people” – as a measure of
fundamental legitimacy discussed above – the United States Constitution would
seem to possess no greater legitimacy than any Act of Congress. The general
population had about as much to do with one as the other, and in both cases
delegated their sovereign authority to elected representatives. Indeed, when
one takes into account the manner by which the states originally sent delegates
to Philadelphia in 1787, the figurative distance between “the People” and the
Constitution is even greater than between the former and any statute passed by
Congress. Federal laws were to be drafted in part by Representatives that the
voters of a given district chose themselves; the Constitution was drafted by
delegates that were commissioned by state legislators, which were in turn elected
by the voting public of the relevant jurisdiction. That the former included an
extra step or filter between the American people and the final draft of the
Constitution – i.e. the state legislatures – would seem to give the lie to
Hamilton’s stated understanding that said document more closely embodied the
popular will than an everyday Congressional statute.
Of course Hamilton was aware of these facts. To be otherwise
wold have required a degree of wilful ignorance on his part. Having labored
along with his fellow delegates for four months in the heat of a sweltering
Philadelphia summer in 1787, he need only have cast his gaze around the
interior of the Pennsylvania State House to know for certain that “the People”
were hardly in evidence. And yet, his position in Federalist No. 78 – that the
Constitution better represented the will of the general population than a given
law passed by Congress – was not wholly without merit. Having possessed some
knowledge of the basic dimensions of the proposed federal government, Hamilton
would have been aware that the first meeting of the newly-reconstituted United
States Congress would have been host to something less than one hundred total
members. Within that number, though every state would be entitled to two Senators,
some possessed population enough for only a single Representative (like
Delaware or Rhode Island) while others stood to elect as many as six (New York
and Maryland), eight (Pennsylvania and Massachusetts), or ten (Virginia). In
consequence, a statute passed by Congress would require the approval of
fourteen Senators and between twenty-nine and thirty-three Representatives –
forty-three to forty-seven men, all told – in order to become law.
By comparison, from the selection of delegates to the final vote
for ratification, the drafting and approval of the Constitution involved in
some fashion or other the discretion or input of every state legislature –
easily several hundred men, if not over one thousand – the knowledge and
expertise of the fifty-five delegates in attendance at Philadelphia, the approval
of the members of the contemporary Continental Congress, and the consideration
of the combined attendees – all one thousand six hundred and forty-eight of
them – of every state convention. Therefore, though he absolutely did not have
access to all of these figures, Hamilton was nevertheless correct in his
assertion that the approved Constitution would enjoy the effective sanction –
or at least reflect in some way the input – of a far greater number of American
citizens than any Act of Congress. This was true in the details as well as the
broad strokes. More Delawareans – by a margin of thirty-five to three – would
have a hand in the Constitution than in a given Congressional statute; more
Georgians, as well, and New Yorkers, and Virginians. Not only was this an
accurate assessment in 1788, when Hamilton originally made his case, but it
remains true in 2017. The current membership of Congress, at five hundred and
thirty-five, is still easily outstripped by the upwards of two thousand people
who in some way gave their approval to and facilitated the adoption of the
United States Constitution. While admitting once more that the truth was
somewhat more complicated than he made it out to be, it would nonetheless seem
fair to credit Hamilton for correctly describing the soon-to-be supreme
governing document of the United States as better reflecting the will of “the
People” than any law to be passed by Congress.
All that being said, the logic behind Hamilton’s rhetorical
association of the proposed constitution with “the People” was almost certainly
of a more cynical nature, and as noted above likely reflected a strategic choice
on the part of the Framers. Consider, as evidence that the authors of the
Constitution were not solely concerned with their creation receiving the widest
sanction possible, that they did not request that the various states submit the
document to a popular referendum. While an uncommon practice in the 18th
century United States – mainly for logistical reasons – such a direct resort to
the general population was not wholly unheard of. Rhode Island, for instance,
submitted the finished draft of the proposed federal constitution to the people
of the Ocean State – who promptly rejected it – rather than move straight to a
ratifying convention in the early months of 1788. And several years earlier,
Massachusetts had likewise submitted its proposed 1778 constitution – which
failed to pass muster – and a revised attempt in 1780 – which succeeded – to
the consideration of its citizens. Therefore, though it would have entailed a
significant outlay of time, resources, and manpower, the notion of scheduling a
series of state referenda on the merits of the proposed constitution would not
have been beyond the realm of possibility. While the results may not have been
swiftly calculated, there could seemingly be no question that they would
represent the unequivocal opinion of the American people.
That the Framers instead recommended the calling of a series
of ratifying conventions would thus seem to speak to a less obvious motivation
than a desire for their work to be widely considered and (hopefully) widely
approved. Taking into consideration the experiences and writings of men like
Hamilton, James Madison, James Wilson, and even George Washington – Framers,
all – in the 1770s and 1780s, two conclusions would seem to suggest themselves
on that score. First, it seems likely that the majority of the Framers did not
trust the state legislatures to approve the proposed constitution on their own.
To do so would surely have been the simplest method of reviewing said document,
and may in fact have acted as something of a salve to the various state
governments whose members surely did not relish the thought of transferring
some portion of their authority to a strong central government. That being
said, where jealous state functionaries didn’t reject out of hand the loss of
autonomy embodied by the proposed constitution, any discussion of the relative
merits of thereof might easily have devolved into yet another chapter in the
ongoing partisan warfare all too common to the various American states in the
post-independence 1780s.
Madison, Wilson, and Hamilton had all borne witness to the
factional acrimony that often plagued the legislative process during their
service in the state assemblies of Virginia, Pennsylvania, and New York,
respectively, and were doubtless eager to avoid having their proposal for a
more effective national government become entangled in the same. Washington,
meanwhile, had seen for himself how destructive partisan conflict within
individual states could become to the broader national interest during his time
as Commander-in-Chief of the Continental Army from 1776 to 1783. More than
once, with the assistance of his aide-de-camp Alexander Hamilton, he had been
forced to wrangle for supplies, arms, and manpower with governors and state
assemblies who seemed more concerned with their own internal disagreements than
their responsibilities to the broader campaign for American independence.
Doubtless Washington – in the late 1780s by far the single most popular man in
America – was similarly keen to avoid involving the state governments in the
question of whether or not to approve the proposed constitution. Thus, it
seemed, having selected delegates to attend the Philadelphia Convention in the
spring of 1787, the role of the state legislatures in the process of drafting
and approving the Constitution had substantively come to a close.
The second conclusion that comes to mind as to why the
Framers preferred to submit the proposed constitution to a series of state
conventions rather than to the people at large or to the state legislatures is
rather more insidious than the first, though no less likely. Whereas the
majority of the contemporary state constitutions had been drafted and approved
by the relevant legislature, thus making them alterable by said legislature on
the same terms as any normal act of law, assembling a special convention in
every state for the purpose of approving the proposed constitution effectively
placed the resulting document beyond the reach of any existing institutions.
Unlike the New York General Assembly or the Massachusetts General Court, which
were perpetual bodies, the ratifying conventions were entirely contingent. As
per the instructions submitted by the Framers to the Continental Congress in
1787, their members were to be elected, to assemble, to consider the proposed
constitution, to vote on it, and then to disperse. Delegates were to be chosen
by rules determined by the individual states – many chose to relax their
franchise restrictions so that more than just property owners could vote and
stand for election – and once dispersed were never expected to meet again.
Indeed, no mechanism existed that would allow them to do so – neither the
Constitution nor the various state governments recognized their existence, and
doubtless the supporters of ratification would have cried foul if their
opponents attempted to re-assemble the conventions for the purpose of offering
revisions or amendments.
By enforcing these terms upon the various states –
ratification through one-off conventions – the Framers effectively created what
every political strategist at some point or another dreams of: a temporary
constituency. Unlike the general public – whose memory was either too long or
too short for comfort – or the state legislatures – whose priorities were very
much their own – the state conventions would have no institutional history, no
set agenda, and no ability to second guess or revoke their decisions once they
had been made. While it was unavoidable that some of their members would come
from among the existing political classes – many state lawmakers, current and
former members of the Continental Congress, and state jurists were elected to
the various state conventions – they were more likely to be non-partisan
affairs than the existing state assemblies, and more likely to count
politically inexperienced farmers, merchants, and small business owners among
their numbers. Such a varied composition made these ad-hoc assemblies more
likely to consider the proposed constitution on its own merits and less likely
to become bogged down by discussions that were of sole significance to local
political circles. Most important of all, however, was their temporary nature.
Once the conventions had rendered their collective verdict
on the proposed constitution and voted to adjourn, there existed no formal
means by which they might be resurrected. As per the directions formulated by
the Framers, these contingent entities could only vote for their Constitution
or against it. Having recorded their vote, they effectively ceased to exist,
and in a legal sense ceased to possess any further authority or legitimacy.
This was true whether the requisite nine states chose to ratify the draft
document or not, and in the event of the former left no opportunity for any
further input into the disposition of the newly-reconstituted national government.
Having been approved, the text of the Constitution itself – Article V, to be
precise – provided the only means by which the American people could seek to
alter their supreme governing document. The state conventions, as it happened, were
to play no part in the process that was laid out therein, and were thereby to
be entirely cast aside once their purpose had been fulfilled. This, more than
the size or the political sensibilities of their membership, was doubtless what
the Framers most favoured about the ratifying conventions. They were, by their
nature, ephemeral. They were also mildly extralegal, possessing no further
authorization than the instructions sent to the Continental Congress and to the
states by the Philadelphia Convention. They existed to suit the exigency of the
moment and were thereafter of no consequence.
For Alexander Hamilton and his fellow advocates of the
proposed constitution, this fact presented a tremendous advantage. Provided
that the majority of the state conventions voted to approve, further
alterations to said document could only come via the aforementioned mechanism
spelled out therein. The result was like some sort of political magic trick. Before
ratification, the state conventions possessed the collective authority to
create to dismiss a tremendously powerful central government. After
ratification – with a puff of smoke and a muttered incantation – the
conventions were rendered meaningless. Not only would they cease to exist, but
even the means by which they were summoned into existence would cease to be
valid. Thus freed from having to continually appease or thwart the evolving
concerns of a collection of thirteen elected bodies – a freedom which could not
have been claimed had the state legislatures been allowed the privilege of
reviewing the Constitution – the proponents of the new national government had
only to contend with the codified amending formula that many of them had
personally helped draft. In addition to representing an exceedingly shrewd and
effective form of legal bait-and-switch – i.e. the Framers created a set of
rules that favored their goals and then convinced their fellow countrymen to
play by them – this outcome arguably permitted people like Hamilton to freely
indulge in the rhetorical association of the Constitution and “the People.”
Of course, in the
aftermath of the approval of the proposed constitution, the members of the
various state ratifying conventions would know who they were. More than likely
their neighbors would know as well, having recently voted for them, and barring
any unforeseen accidents it was likely that most of them would live for a
number of years beyond their brief terms of service. All this being true,
however, did not make it possible for the conventions to be reconvened. Their
task having been completed, the delegates therein would be once more subsumed
into the general population. In consequence, and because neither state law nor
the Constitution recognized their office, there was no more exact way to refer
to the ratifying conventions in perpetuity than by acclaiming them as “the
People” of the United States. Thus, without making any claims that were wholly
or explicitly false, Hamilton could define the Constitution in Federalist No.
78 as “the will of the People,” “the intention of the People,” and the legal
embodiment of “the People themselves.” This, too, suited Hamilton’s momentary
goal of setting the document in question against the authority of the proposed
federal legislature – and thereby carving out a space for the judiciary in the
federal balance of power. That being said, it also indisputably belied the far
more complex relationship that existed – and would come to exist – between the
American people, the states, and the federal government.
No comments:
Post a Comment