Something
occurred to me the other day.
In spite of the attention that
certain institutions within the United States government as rule seem to enjoy
- in spite of how much time and energy pundits and partisans seem to expend
monitoring them, attempting to predict their actions, or developing strategies
around them - these same institutions are not always very well understood. Take
the Electoral College as a case in point. Party tacticians and political
commentators have come to rely on it behaving a certain way. They create
predictive maps, and run through the possible effects of media buys and
campaign stops, and in many cases spend their entire careers attempting to
determine how best to bend the system to a particular outcome. And yet, nearly
without fail, every four years the purpose and the efficacy of the Electoral
College are called into question. For every person who sings its praises, and
claims that it represents the unquestionable will of the Framers of the
Constitution, another will describe it as a meaningless complication of the
democratic process that demands either reform or nullification. The Supreme
Court, I think, occupies much the same popular mind-space. Its rulings are
either praised or reviled, its role either championed or denigrated. Some
acclaim its members as the selfless arbiters of the United States Constitution,
while others castigate them for presuming to substitute their own will for that
of the American people's elected representatives. This latter cohort asks
probing questions: Who are these nine black-robed eminences? What gives them
the right to decide what is and is not law? If the United States really is a
democracy, why aren’t they elected?
Being able to
answer these kinds of inquires in anything like a definitive way would seem
like an essential first step in having a constructive discussion about the role
of the federal judiciary and whether or not it continues to fulfill a useful
purpose in American life. As it stands, its supporters and detractors seem
intent on talking past each other. They lack a framework of consensus that
might otherwise provide structure to their debate. This is, to say the least, a
distressing state of affairs. After all, without a shared premise – an
agreed-upon description of the ideal role of the United States Supreme Court –
the door may well be opened the destructive contortion of the federal judiciary
from non-partisan legal arbiter to tool of majoritarian tyranny. Luckily, there
are resources of which the American people can avail themselves that have long
served to provide a sense of clarity and focus to discussions of deep
constitutional significance. I speak, of course, of the Federalist Papers –
those indispensable policy essays, penned by some of the finest minds from
among the Founding Generation, which collectively explore and explain at length
just about every aspect of the pre-amendment United States Constitution. In
particular, I mean to draw the attention of my readers to Federalist No. 78,
written by the redoubtable Alexander Hamilton with the intention of answering
some of the criticisms leveled by Anti-Federalist pamphleteers at the federal
judiciary that the Framers had designed. No. 78 answers many of the questions
posed above, and in so doing demonstrates a degree of relevance to the
political discourse of the 21st century that belies its publication
date over two hundred years past.
Though brief – clocking in at just twenty-one paragraphs –
and in fact only the first of six essays – Nos. 78 to 83 – Hamilton wrote on
the topic of the federal judiciary, No. 78 nevertheless provides essential
insight into the role that the Framers originally intended the Supreme Court to
fulfill. In it, Hamilton discussed the need for Justices to hold life tenure –
i.e. service during good behavior – the logic of judicial review, and the
reasons he felt it was necessary to make the Court a co-equal branch of the
federal government. Because these qualities are absolutely foundational to the
way that the Court functions, and have also been some of the focus points of
popular debate on the subject, No. 78 may fairly be characterized as a kind of
primer on the role of the Supreme Court, the reason for its existence, and the intentions
of its creators. In addition, because this same essay makes reference to some
of the precedents – British and American alike – upon which the concept of a
national judiciary was based, it may also be seen as further evidence of the
complex origins – intellectually, politically, and socially – of American
republican government. Federalist No. 78, if read aloud on the floor of the
United States Senate or distributed as handbills to every citizen and permanent
resident, may not quell recurrent debates about which touchy social topics the
Supreme Court should or should not address, the extent of its authority, or the
procedures under which it operates. But at the very least, familiarity with the
text therein may at least serve to settle once and for all debate over why the
Court exists and what its creators were thinking when they designed it.
But let’s back off a moment and make a few things clear
before we proceed.
Because this series has already provided, at various points,
a reasonably detailed biography of Alexander Hamilton and an explanation of the
purpose and effect of the Federalist Papers, it would seem of little use to
reiterate here anything but the most essential points. To that end, it ought to
be noted that Federalist No. 78 was originally published on May 28th,
1788 in the state of New York, that eight of the requisite nine states had at
that point ratified the Constitution, and that Hamilton was at that time a
practicing lawyer and a member of the New York State Assembly. He was chosen,
along with fellow New Yorkers Robert Yates (1738-1801) and John Lansing, Jr.
(1754-1829) to attend the Philadelphia Convention in the spring of 1787, and
once his colleagues departed in protest of what was being discussed – Yates and
Lansing did not feel that the Convention had the right to recommend a new form
of government for the United States – became the Empire State’s sole
representative in the ongoing discussions. In spite of the freedom such a
position would seem to entail, however, Hamilton’s contributions to the
finished draft of the Constitution were relatively limited. His various
proposals, while patiently considered by his fellow delegates, were almost
universally rejected as being overly aristocratic – a President and Senate each
elected for life, state governors appointed by the chief executive, etc.
Nevertheless, Hamilton considered the completed document a tremendous
improvement over the existing Articles of Confederation, appended his name to
the final draft, and set about promoting its ratification by the various state
conventions.
On the topic of high courts in the late 18th
century Anglo-American world, a fair bit more ought to be said. After all, the
Framers did not draw the framework and logic of the Supreme Court from whole
cloth. Rather, they sought to combine elements of existing judicial bodies,
tempered with lessons from English, British, and even recent American history,
with the aim of synthesizing an institution that combined consistency with
innovation. In consequence, and in order to better understand exactly which
functions the Framers expected a high court to perform, it would seem a
worthwhile exercise to examine, if briefly, some of the antecedents of the United
States of America’s federal judiciary.
As per usual, Britain almost certainly looms largest in
terms of the influence of its history, politics, and culture upon the Founding
Generation. By the end of the 18th century, the British court system
was, at least on the surface, highly specialized, with cases being heard at the
national level by the Court of Chancery (tasked with hearing petitions for
writs or injunctions), the Court of the King’s Bench (to do with matters
concerning the Crown) the Court of Common Pleas (ruling on suits between
individuals), the Court of the Exchequer (tasked with weighing appeals), or the
High Court of Admiralty (with jurisdiction over maritime law). While each of
these institutions possessed its own set of traditions and procedures, and had
been created to meet a specific need within the sphere of English
jurisprudence, beginning in the 17th centuries their functions became
increasingly difficult to distinguish. This trend further intensified in the 18th
century, with the Court of Chancery, the Court of the Exchequer, the Court of
Common Pleas, and the Court of the King’s Bench at various times hearing the
same kinds of cases and citing each other’s rulings as precedent. The result
was a high degree of redundancy, procedural confusion, and corruption. The
Exchequer, for example, gradually took on the role of court of last resort,
from which a petitioner could appeal to the House of Lords only with difficulty.
The Court of Chancery, by comparison, possessed a far more robust appeals
mechanism, and was often preferred by potential litigants as a result. In
consequence of minor distinctions like these, certain courts became more highly
favored than others, received more business, accrued more prestige, and
attracted better talent.
In addition to the fragmented nature of the 18th
century British court system – as compared to that which was erected in the
American republic under the Constitution – justices in Britain also lacked what
would become perhaps the single most important power at the disposal of the
United States Supreme Court. Namely, they were incapable of nullifying statutes
that had been ratified by Parliament and made law by royal assent. There were –
and to this day there are – several reasons for this. The first is perhaps the
most obvious: unlike the United States of America, Britain has no written
constitution against which Acts of Parliament might be measured. Rather, the
British Constitution is a kind of philosophical or legal concept whereby every
act of law still in force – from the Magna Carta to bills passed by the Commons
yesterday – is considered to form part of an unorganized but still binding
whole. Thus, when a statute is adopted by Parliament which contravenes an
existing law, the latter is simply overwritten. This understandably obviates
any need for judicial intervention, and also highlights the second reason that
judicial review is not a recognized legal concept in Great Britain: the
principle of Parliamentary Supremacy.
In reaction to a series of events stretching across the 17th
and 18th centuries – i.e. the English Civil War (1642-1651) and the
Restoration (1660), the Glorious Revolution (1688-1689), the Act of Settlement (1701),
and the Acts of Union (1707) – the British Parliament gradually, and later
formally, adopted a set of norms and doctrines intended to counter the
discretionary authority of either the Crown or members of the judiciary
appointed by the same. As particularly embodied by the Bill of Rights of 1689
and the aforementioned Act of Settlement, it became generally recognized that
Parliament was permitted to make law touching upon any subject, that no law
passed by one Parliament could not be subsequently repealed or altered by
another, and that no legitimate Act of Parliament could be nullified by the
ruling of a court. Combined, these principles solidified the role of Parliament
as the sole and supreme maker of law in Britain. As Parliament was held to
embody the will of the British people and acted as the guardian of their
rights, Parliamentary Supremacy therefore guaranteed that said people the only
legitimate source of political authority. While unrepresented in Parliament –
and thus theoretically exempt from its authority – the Glorious Revolution and
its implications loomed large in the 17th and 18th
century Anglo-American cultural consciousness, and helped condition the way
American colonists from Massachusetts to Georgia understood the relationship
between their own governments, Parliament, and the Crown.
As discussed in past
entries in this series, however, the realities of life in 17th and
18th century British America often shaped the expectations of
residents therein in ways that defied or rejected the received knowledge of
contemporary British political culture. Unlike Britain proper, the various
colonial governments were defined by written charters, granted by the Crown and
capable of being amended or nullified only by that same authority. In theory,
the existence of these charters placed the colonial governments beyond the
remit of Parliament – as a set of contracts between the monarch and his/her
subjects in particular regions of North America, they could not be countermanded
or repealed by a Parliament which had no part in their creation. That being
said, Parliament generally claimed the right to legislate for the colonies – the
so-called “Declaratory Act” of March, 1766 made this sentiment explicit by
asserting that the British legislature possessed, “Full power and authority to make
laws and statutes of sufficient force and validity to bind the colonies and
people of America […] in all cases whatsoever” – while the relationship between the various settlements of British
America and the Crown were mediated by a body within the Privy Council whose
members were universally sitting or former members of the House of Common or
the House of Lords. Citizens of British America were therefore placed in the
unique position of recognizing, owing loyalty, and paying taxes to two separate
governments – one which was codified and unalterable except by a centralized
authority, and another which was uncodified, unrepresentative, and wholly
exempt from any limitations on its ability to make law. Parliament could
theoretically do nothing to alter the form or function of the various colonial
governments, while the colonial governments were likewise wholly incapable of
challenging the legislation adopted and enforced by Parliament. Neither the
Crown nor the courts could intercede on behalf of the colonies, and in such
cases the citizens of British America were left entirely without recourse.
No comments:
Post a Comment