Section
nine of the Ordinance defined the operation of the electoral franchise in a
similar fashion to section four’s description of inheritance law – i.e. by
forging a rough consensus between the at-times conflicting laws of the various
states. As the previous discussion of entail and primogeniture made note, this
process involved adhering to certain broad commonalities while disregarding
specific exceptions. For instance, as was the norm within the Anglo-American
world at the end of the 18th century, residents of the Northwest
Territory would face age, residence, and property qualifications in order to
either vote in or stand for elections to the lower house of the local assembly.
Almost all of the states observed some variation on this basic framework,
disagreeing mainly upon the quantity or value of property qualifying an
individual to elect or be elected.
Fair
warning: here is where things get complicated.
Under the terms of Georgia’s 1777 constitution, for example,
candidates for the lower house of the state legislature were required to be
twenty-one years of age or older, members of the Protestant faith, and, “Possessed
in their own right of two hundred and fifty acres of land, or some property to
the amount of two hundred and fifty pounds.” Maryland’s 1776 constitution
followed broadly similar lines, requiring lower house members to be, “Above
twenty-one years of age, and having, in the State, real or personal property
above the value of five hundred pounds current money,” while New Jersey’s
constitution from the same year decreed that those standing for election to the
state house of assembly must needs have been, “For one whole year next before
the election, an inhabitant of the county he is to represent, and worth five
hundred pounds proclamation money, in real and personal estate, in the same
county [.]” In terms of who was
entitled to cast a vote, most of the states again followed the same broad
pattern, in this case observing a property qualification that was lower than
that which qualified a citizen to stand for election. New Jersey’s constitution
accordingly limited the franchise to residents of the state, “Who are worth
fifty pounds proclamation money […] and have resided within the county in which
they claim a vote for twelve months immediately preceding the election [.]”
Maryland’s constitution likewise granted a vote to,
All
freemen, above twenty-one years of age, having a freehold of fifty acres of
land, in the county in which they offer to vote [or] having property in this
State above the value of thirty pounds current money, and having resided in the
county, in which they offer to vote, one whole year next preceding the election
[.]
Notable within some these excerpts is
the use of the terms “real” and “personal” in reference to property. Within the
common law tradition, real property is a subset of land that has been improved
by the addition of buildings, infrastructure, or other features which might add
to its value. Real property is immovable and illiquid – its full value cannot
be quickly and easily redeemed – but stable. Personal property conversely
refers, at least in the context of 18th century America, to moveable
assets like farming implements, livestock, or other goods of value not considered
to be part of a landed estate.
By tying the electoral franchise to
a property valuation that was either real or personal, the framers of a number
of the original state constitutions demonstrated a willingness to envision the
body of voters and/or public officials as encompassing more than just the
landed elite. While granting that these kinds of regulations still excluded
large swathes of the respective state populations, it remains a noteworthy
symbol of the evolving nature of American citizenship during the Revolutionary
era that such allowances were made at all. In addition to practically enlarging
the electorate, as well as the talent pool of prospective lawmakers, efforts
like this to subtly widen the franchise implied something significant about the
way Americans envisioned the contours of their respective political
communities. The administration of public affairs – the central purpose of a
republican government – were not to remain the sole province of an aristocratic
landed gentry, it seemed. Rather, they were to embrace those members of society
whose personal wealth – landed or otherwise – denoted their establishment and
investment in the community whose future they desired to shape. For its time,
this was a relatively progressive vision of what constituted the most vital
interests in a given society and one which was no doubt intended as a partial
rejection of the restrictive, rigid, and highly corrupt electoral practises of
contemporary Great Britain.
As aforementioned, the Northwest
Ordinance followed a similar pattern to many of the states in setting out which
of its residents could vote in and/or stand for legislative elections. The
ninth section thereof declared that individuals desiring to be elected to the
lower house of the territorial legislature were required to be a citizen of any
one of the existing states and a resident of the district they were hoping to
represent, or else a resident of said district for at least three years, and in
either case, “Shall likewise hold in his own right, in fee simple, two hundred
acres of land within the same.” This definition of the electoral franchise
would seem most similar to that cited above from Georgia’s first constitution,
varying mainly by requiring a slightly smaller parcel of land (two hundred
acres instead of two hundred and fifty). The comparable clauses of Maryland’s
and New Jersey’s constitution meanwhile differ in that their respective
property requirements were enumerated in a specific monetary amount, but they
too adhered to the same basic principle of personal wealth as a condition of
political participation. The decisions regularly faced by legislators were too
weighty to entrust to people lacking a material investment in their community,
or so the logic went. People who rented property and owned little of value
could be swayed by promises of wealth or favor, and were potentially transitory.
Thus, the framers of a number of state constitutions and of the Northwest Ordinance
seemed to agree that only people of independent means could be relied upon to
serve the public good.
This line of thought extended also
into the realm of delineating electors from non-voting citizens. Returning
again to section nine of the Ordinance, the final clause accordingly states,
That a
freehold in fifty acres of land in the district, having been a citizen of one
of the states, and being resident in the district, of the like freehold and two
years residence in the district, shall be necessary to qualify a man as an
elector.
As with Maryland and New Jersey, the
qualification for the electoral franchise in the Northwest Territory was less
severe than that which conditioned election to public office. As in the states,
this was doubtless understood as an admission that selecting a representative
legislator, while still far from a trifling responsibility, did not require the
same quality of character or social standing as properly befit the legislator
themselves. Worth noting, with this thought process in mind, is the fact that Maryland
and the territory both required prospective voters to possess fifty acres of
land in freehold, and all three jurisdictions cited specific residence
requirements attached to the county or district wherein voting was to take
place. Congress, it seemed, was of a mind with a number of the states as to who
could stand for election and who could do the electing. It consequently follows
that the former was inclined in 1787 to recreate or transpose the kinds of
political communities that existed in some of the states – defined by the
connection between property, wealth, and public service – in the vast and
verdant territory they themselves were to administer for the foreseeable
future.
Not
every state in 1787 was home to political communities thus defined, however. While
property ownership was perhaps the most common condition on office holding and
the electoral franchise in the contemporary United States, it was not the only
condition applied across that nation’s thirteen integral jurisdictions. In some
states, the regulations defining who could vote and who could receive votes
were a fair deal more complicated. This was owed in part to the simple fact
that the Northwest Territory lacked an elected upper house – a body which in
the states tended function under its own specific electoral rules – as well as
to certain geographic and demographic distinctions. While the former represents
a logistic reality – a land of settlers on the frontier of the United States,
the Northwest Territory could not be expected to contain sufficient numbers of
men sufficiently propertied to comprise an elected upper house – the latter
arguably had more to do with history, culture, and social custom.
North Carolina, for example,
separated the electoral franchise into individuals living in a county who could
vote for members of the state House of Commons (freemen at least twenty-one
years old, with a year’s residence in the relevant county and a record of
having paid public taxes) and individuals living in a town who could vote for
members of the state House of Commons (freemen otherwise entitled to vote in a
county, or those with at least a year’s residence in a town and a record of
having paid public taxes, provided that the former did not also attempt to vote
in the county in which they qualified). Complicated though this may sound – and
may in fact have been – there was some amount of logic to it. Major towns in
states like North Carolina and Virginia were often long-established hamlets
with origins dating back to the 17th century. Recognition of their
antiquity and the accompanying political rights were consequently common
features of the relevant state constitutions that were written in the late
1770s. Allowing un-landed taxpayers to vote in lower house elections was
conversely quite progressive, and also somewhat less explicable. Presumably the
framers of North Carolina’s first constitution determined that the House of
Commons would benefit from having as large a constituency as possible. Then
again, this provision may also have been intended to recognize the customary
privileges of the state’s landless urbanites. Though lacking sprawling country
homes in any of the state’s many counties, the merchants and shipping magnates
of towns like Wilmington and Charlotte were far from insignificant to the
political and economic order. Recognizing their taxed personal assets rather
than just their real estate thus likely seemed an acceptable concession between
their own social class and that of the landed elite.
New York laid down a set of
franchise restrictions in its own inaugural constitution that were only
slightly less complicated than those practiced in North Carolina, but which
also made allowance for certain of that state’s unique features. The relevant
clause started of simply enough, stating,
That every
male inhabitant of full age, who shall have personally resided within one of
the counties of this State for six months immediately preceding the day of
election, shall, at such election, be entitled to vote for representatives of
the said county in assembly [.]
To this very unambiguous
qualification, however, the framers of New York’s governing charter added a
series of stipulations unmatched in their specificity by the comparable
franchise regulations of any other state. The theoretical male inhabitant named
above, it first declared, could only vote for members of the lower house of the
state assembly if, during the six month period noted, they had possessed a
freehold worth at least twenty pounds in the relevant county; or had rented a
tenement in the same at the value of forty shillings and had paid taxes to the
state; or was a freeman of the city of Albany; or was made a freeman of the
city of New York on or before October 14th, 1775.
Again, there was reason to this
rhyme, maddeningly particular though it may seem. Being a freeman of a
particular municipality, it bears noting, is a largely antiquated form of civic
honor more or less equivalent to being granted the key to a city. In the 18th
century, freeman status was often accompanied by a set of rights or privileges,
up to and including the ability to vote in the relevant urban electoral
district. Accordingly, the New York constitution’s reference to the freemen of
Albany and New York City was meant to recognize the relatively small number of
individuals who enjoyed specific rights within those jurisdictions. The former,
though not yet the capital in 1787, was one of the oldest chartered towns in
the state, having grown out of a Dutch settlement established in the early 17th
century. This status, along with its population of approximately three thousand
– one tenth of New York City, but greater than the capitals of either Maryland
(Annapolis) or South Carolina (Columbia) – was doubtless felt to entitle it and
its citizens to special recognition. New York City, meanwhile, was (by 18th
century American standards) a metropolis of over thirty thousand whose
unsurpassed influence over the economy of the state at large was doubtless felt
to entitle it to certain specific concession in New York’s first constitution.
Recognizing the franchise rights of its freemen – many of them doubtless
members of the city’s powerful merchant class – was thus but one of a number of
advantages the city derived from its prominence, its size, and its wealth.
Allowing men to vote who merely
rented a forty shilling tenement was doubtless also seen to benefit New York
City within the political order that the state’s 1776 constitution established.
Pointing once again to its sheer size – Philadelphia, at approximately
twenty-five thousand in 1787, was the only city in late 18th century
America that came particularly close – there were surely thousands of men
living in what is now the borough of Manhattan in the late 1780s who were old
enough to vote, and politically conscious, but were unable to put together the
funds to purchase property of their own. For reference, forty shillings was
equal to two pounds in 1787, and the average farm income in colonial New York
in the early 1770s was twenty pounds per year. Assuming, then, that the forty
shillings to be paid in rent as a qualification for the franchise was meant to
describe a yearly interval, the renter in question would have been spending
about ten percent of what a farmer made in a year on housing. While this would
doubtless have seemed quite high in the many county towns north of NYC, prices
in the city proper were almost certainly higher on average than in the rest of
the state.
As to why the framers of the 1776
constitution chose to factor this into their considerations when determining
who among their countrymen would possess the franchise, it possibly represented
a concession amongst the rural and urban interests – the wealthy landlords of
Long Island and the Hudson valley against the merchants and stockjobbers of
Manhattan – which between them comprised the upper strata of the Empire State’s
social hierarchy. Because in addition to the landless urbanites of New York
City – a population that the city-dwelling elite doubtless hoped to mobilize on
their behalf – the upstate manor lords also served to benefit from the
enfranchisement of a traditionally dependent population. Namely, these were the
tenant farmers from whom New York’s landed elite derived a large portion of
their income. Owning no real property of their own, they lived in a
pseudo-feudal relationship to their hereditary landlords. As the democratic
impulses unleashed by the Revolution promised effective electoral power in
exchange for securing the franchise for their wards, the upstate landed gentry
doubtless found ample cause to agree with their urban counterparts on the
generous terms previously mentioned in the state’s first post-independence
governing charter. The resulting electoral franchise model, while in many ways
unsuitable for emulation in other jurisdictions, was as valid as the more
straightforward templates practiced in Georgia, or Maryland, or indeed the
Northwest Territory.
Still
other states in 1787 – representatives of which, it bears remembering,
participated in the formulation and approval of the Northwest Ordinance – had
settled upon franchise regulations that were chiefly distinguished by their
Spartan simplicity. Pennsylvania was perhaps the paramount example of this
streamlined ideal. Its 1776 constitution, radical in so many aspects, followed
suit in the terms it laid down for the regulation of elections. To qualify as
an elector, it stated, a freeman need only be twenty-one years of age, have
resided in the state for at least one year before the exact date of the vote,
and have paid public taxes during that time. Those standing for election to the
House of Representatives – the state’s unicameral legislature – were likewise
to fulfill a residence requirement – two years in the city or county in
question, rather than one year in the state – but were evidently exempt from
having either to pay taxes or own property. Thus defined, Pennsylvania’s
electorate in the late 1770s and into the 1780s would have been one of the
largest in the United States, if not the absolute largest, as a proportion of
its overall population. It would also likely have been relatively
well-distributed throughout the state – in cities and towns as well as the
countryside – and thus highly representative of the general population.
Not
being able to point to specific economic or geographic characteristic as the
root cause of specific electoral considerations – if for no other reason than
there were none – it seems likely that Pennsylvania’s lax franchise
requirements had their origin in its distinct history as a political community.
Founded by Quaker William Penn (1644-1718) in 1682, the Province of
Pennsylvania was governed throughout its history by a series of documents, all referred
to as the “Frame of Government.” These charters, drafted by the assembled
notables of the colony, represented a mixture of Penn’s humanist ideals, the
terms of governance spelled out in the royal charter granted by Charles II
(1630-1685), and the often clashing interests of Pennsylvania’s Quaker and
non-Quaker residents. The third of these elements ultimately proved the most
difficult to reconcile, and at various times the percentage of the population
able to vote and/or hold office reflected the ascendancy of either the settled
Quaker landlords or the mainly-urban Protestant immigrant community. This
conflict persisted in various forms throughout the 18th century, and
by the 1770s had in many ways – along with a longstanding guarantee of freedom
of religion – come to define the political culture of Pennsylvania.
Doubtless
exhausted by decade upon decade of communal squabbling over political
preeminence, the framers of Pennsylvania’s 1776 constitution likely welcomed
the chance to establish their independence upon firmly egalitarian footing. The
rhetoric of the ongoing Revolution provided the ideal intellectual grounding
for such an attempt, concerned as it was with lofty concepts like liberty,
justice, and certain self-evident truths. Indeed, the fact that the assembly of
American notables whose statement of purpose was the Declaration of
Independence made its home in Philadelphia – and even met in the colony’s state
house – perhaps helped to concentrate the minds of many Pennsylvanians upon the
deficiencies embodied by their own government and the social and cultural
conflicts they had historically engendered. By wiping away the petty
distinctions that had previously defined their shared political community and
establishing in their place a system of government predicated on a practical
guarantee of individual and collective equality, the citizens and statesmen of
Pennsylvania thus set themselves to a dual purpose. On one hand, they actively
embodied the humanist ideals of the American Revolution in the basic shape and
function of their government, which in a very real way also fulfilled the
egalitarian promise upon which the colony had originally been founded in the 17th
century. And on the other hand, they effectively lay to rest the sectarian
social conflict and the associated distractions and inefficiencies that had
plagued them for nearly a century. Granted, simply opening up the franchise
would not – and in fact did not – solve or prevent every political conflict the
people of Pennsylvania encountered. That being said, the relevant franchise
rules represented a response to the link between electoral politics and
sectarian conflict that was unique to the Keystone State and no less viable for
it.
My
readers can be forgive for asking at the juncture – as I so often give them
cause to – just what this deep dive into the franchise laws of half a dozen
different states has to do with the Northwest Ordinance and the territory it
created. Admitting that we may have ventured a little far into the weeds, there
was, rest assured, a purpose to it. As previously discussed, the Northwest Ordinance was
drafted by the delegates to Congress in attendance as of July, 1787. These men
had been chosen to represent the states from which they came in the national
council of the United States of America, and thus embodied both the particular
interests of their individual communities and the collective interests of the
country at large. In some respects, the way that each of them understood law,
and land, and electoral politics varied significantly. In spite of certain
broad commonalities, inheritance law and election law functioned quite
differently between states like New York, and Pennsylvania, and Georgia, and
North Carolina. In the normal course of the business of Congress, this would likely not have mattered much. The fact that forty shilling renters in
Manhattan could vote in lower house elections while their counterparts in
Savannah lacked the same privilege had very little to do with defining
interstate commerce regulations or attempting to formulate a trade impost that
a majority of the states might actually abide by. The United States in Congress
Assembled, as the national government was known between 1777 and 1789, didn’t
oversee affairs of domestic concern like elections or estate law, concerning
itself instead with matters of a specifically and exclusively national
character (foreign trade, national defense, diplomacy, etc.).
No comments:
Post a Comment