When Brutus (or Robert Yates, as was
almost certainly the scribe’s true identity) set out to confront the advocates
of the United States Constitution in a series of essays publish in the New York Journal and the Weekly Register in 1787 and 1788, he did
so very much in the spirit of opposition. The Massachusetts compromise, which
allowed ratification to be linked to eventual amendment, had yet to take place
and the object of most Anti-Federalists was at that time to entirely defeat the
ratification effort and force either a second constitutional convention or an
abandonment of the effort altogether. Yates, therefore, had little reason to be
conciliatory or show any admission to the Federalist point of view. Consequently
the tone of the majority of his essays is quite scathing (perhaps a factor in
why they are so memorable), showing a degree of contempt for the at-times vague
language employed by the Constitution and a desire to expose what he perceived
as the Framers self-interest and corruption. Nevertheless, Yates and him
opponents were a part of the same generation of Americans. They’d been raised
and educated in much the same intellectual environment, and in spite of their
economic or cultural distinctions (being wealthy or middling, Dutch or English,
Puritan or Quaker) most drew from the same basic philosophical well. There are,
accordingly, more than a few appeals in Yates’ Brutus II to what would almost
certainly have constituted common ground among members of the Revolutionary
Generation.
Among
the first of these common references that Yates made was in the second
paragraph of Brutus II, and concerned the notion of a social contract and
natural rights. Like John Adams or Thomas Jefferson, Yates seemed keen to
endorse the basic philosophical concept that all societies are based on an
unspoken contract between rulers and ruled. Government is the reaction to
perceived needs; people need protection, from each other and from outsiders,
and so they form communities that provide certain services in exchange for a
voluntary surrender of a portion of each member’s personal sovereignty. “The
common good, therefore,” Yates wrote, “is the end of civil government, and common
consent, the foundation on which it is established.” This is a classic example
of social contract theory, and a concept fundamental to contemporary Western
European philosophy. Though I know I’ve discussed this very concept in a
previous post, some time has passed since then. For that reason, I’d like to
take a moment to delve into a somewhat expanded refresher on the topic of the
social contract.
Natural
law, natural rights and the social contract have been topics of discussion for
centuries, perhaps millennium, among the foremost minds of their respective
generations. From Ancient Greece and India, to Republican Rome and Renaissance
Italy; they were hardly new ideas by the time of Yates and the
Anti-Federalists. That being said, social contract theory as it was understood
by the Revolutionary Generation in America was very much a product of the 17th
and 18th centuries. The thinkers that would likely have resonated
for them the most were Hugo Grotius, Thomas Hobbes and John Locke. Grotius
(1583-1645) was a Dutch jurist, philosopher and statesman who theorised that
every individual possessed certain rights that were not granted to them by
monarchs or political institutions but were inherent to their existence as
human beings. These rights were part of a moral framework that was not based on
a specific religious doctrine, but rather stemmed from a sense of social
acceptability that was born out of consensus. People, Grotius argued, were the
prime sovereign actors in society and their actions were constrained by what
they and their neighbours agreed was suitable behaviour. Hobbes (1588-1679),
English philosopher and polymath, expanded on these ideas in the 1650s and
formulated a more structured social framework than Grotius had imagined in the
1620s. While Hobbes was willing to endorse the notion of natural rights and was
the first to describe the political arrangement between the governed and their
governors as a “social contract,” his description of the concept was quite
rigid. While Hobbes believed that individuals did cede some of their rights
when they recognised the authority of law and government, he did not believe
that these rights remained with the individual. Living within a society, he
asserted, was tantamount to endorsing the authority that made that society
possible; the only way to completely recapture ones rights would be to exit the
social contract completely by living outside society in a state of complete
anarchy.
Locke
(1632-1704), the great English republican luminary, was the social contract
theorist that most educated American in the late-18th century would
have been familiar with and sympathetic towards. It was Locke that described
the more flexible social contract that men like Jefferson fully endorsed, and
that recognised rights and responsibilities on behalf of both the ruled and the
ruler. He believed that the purpose of the state was to act as a neutral judge
between individuals and communities, and to protect the life, liberty and
property of those within its borders. A government that violated these terms
was guilty of breaking the social contract, and thus offered itself up to be
overthrown and replaced. Lockean social contract theory was very much at the
heart of the rights-based ideology expressed by the American Founding Fathers
and was prominently featured in the Declaration of Independence. Locke’s was
not, however, the most recent articulation of the concept that the Founders
would have had access to. Swiss thinker Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) had
developed his own formulation of social contract theory in his 1762 treatise,
the aptly titled Social Contract.
While not as widely known and read in America as Locke, perhaps because he was
both radical and French, Rousseau was still highly influential among a certain
(particularly well-read) percentage of the Revolutionary Generation. His
argument was somewhat more abstract that any of his predecessors, and regarded
the social body as almost an entity unto itself. Law and government, he wrote,
were the product of social consensus and functioned best when individuals
surrendered their wants and desires to the greater good. Representative
government was, to Rousseau, a step in the right direction, but still created a
barrier between people and their government and would need to be eventually
transcended. To most of the Founders, who as they matured had been inundated by
British rights culture, this self-abnegation was a bridge too far. Locke was
their yardstick, and it was in a Lockean mode that Yates set out the beginnings
of his argument in Brutus II.
Though
the Anti-Federalist Papers were certainly an instrument of opposition, in this
case to the proposed Federal Constitution, they were also, like the Federalist
Papers, a tool of persuasion. Yates and his fellow Anti-Federal authors wrote
for an audience whose minds they were intent on swaying to their cause. Because
of the way the Constitution had to be ratified by specially-formed conventions prior
to its adoption this was far from an ineffective tactic. And in Brutus II Yates
demonstrated one of the simplest ways he appealed to the reason of his readers,
by establishing a sense of agreement and consensus between them and him. The
social contract was a commonly understood concept among the class of men who
were in attendance at the state ratifying conventions. If Yates could show how
aligned the opinions of his audience already were with his own, convincing them
to overcome the remaining differences was hopefully made all the simpler.
It
was doubtless in this mode that Yates also argued for the inclusion of a bill
of rights in the federal constitution by citing past examples taken from both
the British and American contexts. This was, in fact, the main object of Brutus
II. Yates, among many others, felt the Constitution’s lack of a clearly defined
series of legal protections for individual rights was highly suspect. For
something that had formerly been highly revered in America (as the idea of a
bill of rights certainly was), such a conspicuous absence struck many of the document’s
critics as a naked attempt by those that stood to wield the powers granted to
the new government to erase any legal roadblocks to their eventually assuming
tyrannical authority. As the Anti-Federalists and Yates in particular were
quick to point out, there existed in the 1780s much precedent to be found in
favour of the inclusion of a bill of rights, or something like it. English legal
history furnished two influential examples, the Magna Carta and the 1689 Bill
of Rights. The former was drafted by a collection of rebellious barons in 1215
and forced on a reluctant King John I in exchange for allowing him to maintain
his throne. Among other things, most having to do with now-obscure feudal
privileges, the Magna Carta guaranteed certain rights to free-men (people not
in service to a feudal lord) and the church, ensured standard practises in
trial matters, and restricted the levying of fines so as not to endanger a
person’s livelihood.
In spite of the fact that it
remained in force until well into the 19th century, however, the
significance of the Magna Carta is largely symbolic. Indeed, the charter that
was forced on John I in 1215 was almost immediately annulled by the crown;
subsequent versions were issued by later monarchs in an attempt to placate the
nobility, though these later Magna Cartas no longer contained the provisions
that represented a direct challenge to the power of the monarchy. For example,
the earliest drafts of the document included a provision that would have
allowed the creation of a council of nobles who could meet in order to review
the monarch’s behaviour. If it was found that the king/queen was in violation of
the rights granted by the charter, the council could authorise the seizure of
crown property. This clause was highly objectionable to John I and his
successors, and subsequent versions of the Magna Carta (most notably the 1297
draft that was submitted to and approved by parliament) omitted it entirely.
Nevertheless, the idea of the Magna Carta, that even monarchs were not above
the rule of law and could be bound by their subjects to respect certain rights,
proved highly influential both in Britain and in America. Among other things,
it came to be regarded as the cornerstone of what’s known as the unwritten
British Constitution, and led to the emergence of Parliament as a body that
represented the interests of the kingdom apart from the crown and wielded
significant legal authority on its own.
Over the centuries that followed
the distinct legal authority and identity of Parliament grew and evolved, and
the British tolerance for unchecked monarchical power waned. In 1689, the
overthrow of James II and the installation of his daughter Mary and son-in-law
William as joint monarchs witnessed yet another evolution of the British
Constitution in the direction of codifying the rights of the people and the
restrictions placed on the crown. The subsequent Bill of Rights was, as
previously discussed, the culmination of nearly fifty years of conflict between
Parliament and the monarchy. As a piece of legislation, it enshrined a variety
of individual protections into British law; among them were guarantees of the
freedom to bear arms, freedom of speech, freedom from cruel and unusual
punishment, and prohibitions against royal interference in function of the law.
Symbolically, its significance was perhaps more far-reaching. For Englishmen in
the late-17th century the Bill of Rights confirmed what they already
felt in their hearts; that they were among the freest people in the world and
the most conscious of their rights. Over the course of the 1600s they had faced
down the spectre of absolute monarchy and slain it, and the Bill of Rights was
the great symbol of their victory. Americans, who in the main were of British
heritage, felt this sense of pride no less than their brothers across the
Atlantic. Among the Founding Generation, the Bill of Rights was one of the most
highly regarded and widely cited examples of the British freedoms the
revolutionaries felt had been taken from them and which they hoped to reclaim.
No comments:
Post a Comment