Because Federalist No. 1 was
really only intended to introduce the series of essays that followed, it lacks
much of the detailed discussion of the text of the Constitution, or the
philosophical or historical reflections that characterize many of the more
well-known Federalist Papers. It’s relatively brief, at only nine paragraphs,
and keeps its references to individuals, groups, or scenarios rather vague.
There are, for instance, no allusions to philosophers, no mentions of Greece or
Rome, and no specific critiques of the people or bodies that had prospered by
the weakness of the Articles of Confederation, and which would no doubt have
found the proposed Constitution particularly threatening. But in spite of this
overall simplicity of approach, or perhaps because of it, Federalist No. 1
stands out as both an insightful critique of the weaknesses of American
government and political culture in the 1770s and 1780s, and a remarkably
even-handed caution against political extremism or populism, all delivered with
Hamilton’s characteristic matter-of-fact conviction.
It important to remember that
Hamilton served in a number of political and military offices over the course
of his adult life that combined to give him a distinct perspective on the way
the American government under the Articles of Confederation functioned. During
his time as an army logistics officer in the 1770s he became acquainted with
how narrow-minded some state government could be when donations of money or
resources were asked of them, and how difficult it was to convince them of the
existence of a larger national interest that superseded their local demands. He
witnessed the same conflict from the other side as a member of Congress in the
1780s, during which he was continually confronted with the inability of the
federal government to enforce its decisions or fund its initiatives, however
well-intention or devised. Finally, his time as a delegate to the New York
Legislature showed him first-hand how easily state politics had become dominated
by populists and demagogues who sought mainly to enrich themselves by catering
to the most basic impulses of the population, offering to redistribute land,
cancel debts, and print dangerous quantities of easily devalued paper money. While
it thus stands to reason that Hamilton was speaking from a place of experience in
Federalist No. 1, it’s also fair to say that his perspective on the need for a
stronger central government was far from unbiased.
His partiality makes itself known
first in the third paragraph of Federalist No. 1, wherein he admitted that
though the proposed constitution had been carefully and thoughtfully crafted
there were likely several classes of men in the states that would oppose its
adoption. They would, he said, “resist all changes which may hazard a
diminution of the power, emolument and consequence of the offices they hold
under the State-establishments.” Though Hamilton was no friend of the state
governments, and during the Philadelphia Convention he even pushed forward
proposals for their virtual abolition, he knew they were too well-loved by
their residents to permit significantly tampering with their authority. The new
constitution, however, proposed to fundamentally alter the balance of power
between the states and the federal government. Under the Articles of
Confederation, the states had really been “in the driver’s seat.” They
conducted most of their own commerce, possessed their own military forces, and
owed taxes to Congress only in theory. While the Constitution didn't propose to
take away most of the powers that the states already possessed, it created a
federal government that was much stronger than under the Articles, and much
more capable of collecting its taxes and enforcing its laws. By portraying the
opponents to this alteration as petty, power-hungry and jealous, Hamilton no doubt
hoped to shake off the distrust of strong central government that had long
persisted in America and depict the proposed federal administration as the
solution to runaway state power, rather than a problem in itself.
Hamilton reiterated on this theme
in the fifth paragraph of Federalist No. 1, wherein he described some of what
he predicted would be the objections to an increase in federal authority. Chief
among them, he envisioned that, “an enlightened zeal for the energy and
efficacy of government will be stigmatized, as the offspring of a temper fond
of despotic power, and hostile to the principles of liberty.” Considering the
historically tense relationship that had existed between the Crown and the
various American colonies, punctuated by at-times violent attempts to either
defy or enforce authority (particularly in the 17th century), this
seems like a reasonable assumption on Hamilton’s part. Indeed, considering how
fundamental to American political culture the debate over federal vs. state
authority has become, his comment here seems quite prescient. In another
observation that seems to blend precedent and foresight, Hamilton cautioned
that, “A dangerous ambition more often lurks behind the specious mask of zeal
for the rights of the people, than under the forbidding appearance of zeal for
the firmness and efficacy of Government.” Once more, without calling on
specific examples, he cast aspersions on what he perceived as the parochial
mindset of the petty state official who would claim to defend the liberty of
the people while distrusting any attempt to limit his authority. No doubt
alluding to the history of Ancient Rome, wherein men who claimed to represent
the common people transformed a republic into an empire, Hamilton made the
further claim that, “Of those men who have overturned the liberties of
republics the greatest number have begun their career, by paying an obsequious
court to the people; commencing Demagogues, and ending Tyrants.” That Napoleon
Bonaparte, one-time defender of the people and later Emperor accomplished this
same transformation in France not twenty years after Federalist No. 1 was
published no doubt struck many as validation of Hamilton’s words, though he did
not live to see it.
What’s so interesting about these
claims, which on the surface seem all too typical of a political debate in
which each side seeks to demonize the motives of the other, is the way in which
their author sought to couple them with a very measured criticism of the idea
of motivation in politics and the way it can often cloud discussions of policy.
While taken ample space to critique the opponents of the Constitution for their
greed and provincialism, Hamilton actually began Federalist No. 1 by invoking
reason as the rightful principle that ought to guide the process of the
document’s adoption. In the second paragraph, he first commented that it would
be proper, considering the weight of the topics under discussion, if the
adoption of the Constitution was, “Directed by a judicious estimate of our true
interests, unperplexed and unbiased by considerations not connected with the
public good.” But he then admits that, “This is a thing more ardently to be
wished, than seriously to be expected,” because the proposed constitution
touched on the interests of far too many people and institutions to be the
subject of purely sober and reasoned debate. In many ways such an admission of
weakness in the face of logic was characteristic of both Hamilton and many of
his compatriots among the Founders and the Framers. One of the reasons the
Constitution was adopted, and structured the way it was, was because men like
Hamilton, Madison, Franklin and Adams had developed a keen sense of the
imperfect nature of man, and the need to create institutional guards against
that imperfection running amok.
What Hamilton did next, though,
was ask his reading audience to attempt to rise above their petty impulses and
see the debate surrounding the Constitution without relation to their own
biases, or those of the major participants in the discussion itself. This was
something most of his contemporaries likely would have acknowledged was next to
impossible, and something that Hamilton approached in his characteristically
meticulous, confident, and forthright manner. To begin, he admitted that wrong
heads were not always motivated by wrong hearts. A person, he claimed, may come
to find themselves on the “wrong” side of an argument through simple
misunderstanding or by having been led astray, and that, “This circumstance, if
duly attended to, would furnish a lesson of moderation to those, who are ever
so much persuaded of their being in the right, in any controversy.” He followed
this with an acknowledgement of a perhaps even more pernicious problem, that
even those that come down of the “right” side of a question were as likely
motivated by personal ambition or avarice as their opponents. These ruminations
on the nature of motivation as a component of political debate accomplished two
things, one intended and the other likely not.
First, provided the readers of
Federalist No. 1 felt themselves willing and able to rise to the challenge,
they paved the way for Hamilton to contextualize the arguments surrounding the
Constitution in terms of simple right and wrong. If motivations could never be
counted on to always correspond to methods, there was no point in taking
account of them. Regardless of who argued for or against, there was a right
answer and a wrong answer. Provided people based their judgements in logic and
not partiality, the right would always triumph. For Hamilton, a master of
rhetoric who was certainly not above manipulating events behind closed doors in
service of what he perceived to be the greater good, this was an ideal way to
frame a political debate. This was surely why he chose to publish the
Federalist Papers under the pseudonym Publius. In addition to it being a
well-worn convention of 18th-century political authorship to publish
under assumed names, it allowed Hamilton and his partners Madison and Jay to
avoid having their reputations overshadow their arguments. Regardless of who
was involved in the discussion or why, the best reasoned argument would emerge
victorious. Being a noted purveyor of well-reasoned arguments, and a man with a
great many political resources at his disposal, this no doubt suited Hamilton
very well indeed.
Second, and probably without
meaning to, Hamilton elevated the debate he was trying to frame. It is, after
all, characteristic of the human condition that no one can every really know
what anyone else is thinking. Words and actions are only a shadow of who a
person really is and what they intend; a representation of their true self, or
the self they are willing to show to the world. Though Hamilton acknowledged
this fundamental truth as a means of setting more favourable terms for himself
and his arguments, it holds weight far beyond what he likely envisioned.
Ironically, in spite of his rather selfish motives, his assertion carries the
ring of truth. It is the “right” answer, though Hamilton was no doubt little
interested in addressing the abstract, philosophical, or existential questions
that such a claim seems to address. This is, among other things, what makes
Federalist No. 1 worthwhile. In the same breath that its author attempted to
discount the biases surrounding the debate he was engaged in, he criticizes his
opponents for their narrow-mindedness and ambition. In the same paragraph that
he tried to argue, for his own purposes, that what a person said was more
important than who they were or what they intended, he exposed a philosophical
truth that speaks to the heart of human existence. It is a strangely
contradictory series of arguments, and yet coming from the pen of Hamilton
seems perfectly in keeping with his political persona and preferred methods.
Federalist No. 1 contains two
further assertions that seem moderate and perceptive, though they were no doubt
deployed in order to advance their author’s ambitions. The first is a criticism
of political parties, made all the more significant by Hamilton’s historical
reputation as an arch-partisan. At the end of the fourth paragraph of
Federalist No. 1, he wrote that, “Nothing could be more ill-judged than that
intolerant spirit, which has, at all times, characterized political parties.
For, in politics as in religion, it is equally absurd to aim at making
proselytes by fire and sword. Heresies in either can rarely be cured by
persecution.” Though political parties as we understand them did not exist in
the United States in the 1780s they would come to be soon enough, hastened in
no small part by the efforts of Hamilton himself. While he no doubt hoped that
this statement would help to portray him and his cause as non-partisan, and
thereby allow him to label his critics as members of a destructive party or faction,
it remains sound, measured advice in any age in which partisan gridlock abounds.
Once more an attempt at rhetorical manipulation carries a seed of wisdom. Also
of interest is Hamilton’s use of a religious metaphor. By comparing the methods
employed by political parties to religious persecution, he was implicitly
relying on his audience to be at least somewhat in favour of freedom of
conscience. This either speaks to Hamilton’s religious views, which were
relatively moderate and coloured by the Enlightenment, or those of his intended
audience in New York and the other battleground states. Likely it speaks to
both.
The second assertion begins the
following paragraph, and is essentially an argument in favour of reason over
emotion in politics. In response to the proposed constitution, Hamilton
predicts that, “A torrent of angry and malignant
passions will be let loose. To judge from the conduct of the opposite parties,
we shall be led to conclude, that they will mutually hope to evince the
justness of their opinions, and to increase the number of their converts by the
loudness of their declamations, and the bitterness of their invectives.”
Considering how closely entwined Hamilton’s fortunes were to become with the so-called
Federalist Party’s, and how bitter the invective that he himself was known to
hurl at his opponents, this might seem like a rather hollow declaration. Over
the course of the 1790s, he did a great deal as a member of the Washington
administration to defame his political rivals, and after his resignation in
1795 worked behind the scenes to solidify his faction’s hold on the executive
power. Indeed, it was his loud declamation of then-President John Adams in 1800
that arguably ended his career as a political operative. For a man of moderation
and patience it was an act of unforgiveable indiscretion to so forcefully
criticize a sitting president, and the leader of his own party at that. But,
for all that, it’s good advice. Political invective can be poisonous to good
policy, in 1787 or in any time thereafter, and though his motivations were far
from pure it’s a point worth making.
No comments:
Post a Comment