As I mentioned, the fundamental
rhetorical basis of Thomas Paine’s Common
Sense is its reliance on plainly observable facts and reasoning that asks
no more of its readers than to exercise their inherent sense of logic – their
(drum roll please) common sense – to judge the quality of its arguments. The
reason for this is because Paine intended his pamphlet for a popular audience.
Unlike Thomas Jefferson, who in the 1770s and 1780s tended to write for people
as well-versed in the classics and Enlightenment philosophy as himself, Paine
chose not to depend on his readers being particularly well-read, well-educated,
or even literate. To do so would have limited the number of those capable of
understanding the ideas he wanted to communicate, and perhaps better than the
Founders themselves Paine understood that for the American Revolution to
succeed it would need to be a popular movement.
Thus the arguments Paine deployed
throughout Common Sense approached
the prospect of independence from Great Britain (at the time of publication in January,
1776 still a topic of debate) less from an abstract philosophical perspective –
concerned with natural rights, natural law, sovereignty and custom – than one
characterized by pragmatism and expediency. Rather than argue that separation
was necessarily a fundamental or objective good, something Paine seemed to more
or less take for granted, his assertions instead focussed on the practical
economic and political benefits of independence and the relative ease with
which it could be achieved. Whereas Jefferson or Adams rationalised
disobedience and armed resistance to British authority as flowing out of the
“right of revolt” described by English political theorist John Locke – whereby
rulers who did not uphold their end of the unspoken social contract could legitimately
be overthrown and replaced – Paine claimed that revolution and independence
were permissible, even desirable, for no more reason than the end result meant
a better life for the average American. He approached this overarching
conclusion from many different directions and deployed many different tools
along the way, from the facts and figures of British naval construction to
basic English and colonial American history. Whatever the avenue of approach,
however, Paine’s tone managed to avoid outright condescension. Rather than
speak down to his audience he phrased his arguments in terms that placed a
premium on clarity, practicality, and simplicity, and made use of references
(Biblical, historical and contemporary) that were eminently accessible to the
average colonial citizen.
Composed of an introduction and
four parts, Common Sense begins by
contemplating the origins of “Government in general” while making certain
specific comments about the unwritten English Constitution. Before delving into
these general remarks, however, Paine’s introduction opened, tellingly, by
exhorting readers to understand that though many of the ideas about to be
discussed at length were both radical and unfamiliar, tradition was not
necessarily a guarantee of goodness or rightness. “A long habit of not thinking
a thing wrong,” Paine wrote, “gives it a superficial appearance of being right,
and raises at first a formidable outcry in defence of custom […] Time makes
more converts than reason.” This admission/admonition by Paine seems to
demonstrate awareness on his part of the task before him in attempting to push
against centuries of accepted wisdom with little more than the force of reason
at the same time that it rather neatly encapsulates one of his overall aims.
By January, 1776, when the first
edition of Common Sense was published
in Pennsylvania, the British (and earlier English) colonization of North
America had been ongoing for over 150 years. Though in that time the relationship
between the colonies themselves and the Crown had not always been particularly
harmonious the 18th century had witnessed a steady period of stable
relations and a general acceptance of the bond between the colonial governments
and post-Glorious-Revolution Britain. Admittedly the events of the 1760s and
1770s had weakened the integrity of this abiding status quo, between the
imposition of unprecedented taxes on basic commodities and the harsh response
to resulting attempts at resistance, but Paine’s task was still far from easy.
The Revolutionary War, which began in April, 1775 with the Battles of Lexington
and Concord, remained confined to Massachusetts and Lower Canada (Quebec) until
June, 1776 with the British invasion of New York. The majority of Americans at
the time of Paine’s writing were thus accustomed to British rule, and to
monarchy in general, and had yet to be touched by the nascent Revolution in a
meaningful, personal way. Common Sense
therefore needed to dissect the basic assumptions of its readers, about how
governments should function and how important their connection to Britain
really was, at the same time it made its case for separation and independence.
To that end, the sixth paragraph
of the first section of Common Sense
contains as straightforward an explanation of the theoretical origin of
government as is likely to be found in any prominent example of 18th-century
philosophy. Neither taking the knowledge of his readers for granted not
doubting their ability to grasp a complex idea if put to them in the right way,
Paine set out very early on in his most influential political tract to
establish a baseline understanding of what the purpose of government was
supposed to be. Specifically, he described government as arising first out of the
need felt by all people for personal security. Collective security, whereby
people depend on each other for mutual protection, followed as a potential
solution, which begat formal structure, delegated administration,
representative government, and some form of democracy. At the core of this
explanation, as Paine phrased it, was an emphasis on the spontaneous nature of
government. It arose not as the consequence of the leadership of a king, as
monarchy would seem to imply, but was generated, nurtured and directed by the
people whose lives and livelihoods it was to serve. As Paine explained it,
because representative government and frequent elections, “will establish a
common interest with every part of the community, they will mutually and naturally
support each other, and on this (not on the unmeaning name of king) depends the
strength of government, and the happiness of the governed.”
This chronicle of the basic evolution of human
civilization, though simply phrased, is not all that different from similar
explanations put forward by philosophers like John Locke in their own political
treatises. The theory that a “social contract” of some sort existed at the core
of all forms of government was a favorite of the European Enlightenment and had
been repeated and refined by any number of contemporary thinkers. Where Paine
differed, in addition to the simplicity and concision of his language, was in
his additional assertion that the validity of the social contract theory of the
origin of government lay precisely in its lack of complexity. “I draw my idea
of the form of government from a principle in nature, which no art can
overturn,” Paine stated, “that the more simple a thing is, the less liable it
is to be disordered, and the easier repaired when disordered.” Doubtless this
was a powerful sentiment to the generation of colonial Americans who had
suffered under the burden of several rounds of controversial taxation and been
forced to endure contending arguments for and against natural rights, regulation
versus revenue, and the unparalleled sovereignty of Parliament. Government,
Paine insisted, should not be so complex as to elude the understanding of those
it was supposed to serve. Rather it should be simple enough to avoid
inefficiency or breakdown and easy to diagnose and repair in the event of the
latter. The manner in which the colonies were governed as appendages of the
British Empire in the 1770s was decidedly far from simple.
Though the various colonies
enjoyed different forms of government themselves, and different relationships
to the Crown, all of them were self-acknowledged subjects of the British
Monarch and his/her heirs. Each colony had a legislature of its own that was
elected via some form of suffrage involving property ownership and each had a
Governor who was either elected by a subset of the colonial population or
appointed by the Crown (or in the case of Pennsylvania, New Jersey and Maryland
by its Lord Proprietor). Technically speaking none of the colonies fell under
the authority of the British Parliament. While George III was acknowledged by
its citizens to be the monarch of the colony of Virginia, Virginia was not
formally a part of the Kingdom of Great Britain. Accordingly the assembled MPs
and Lords in Westminster had no legal right to make law for the colonies. To
that end, the administration of Britain’s various North American colonies was
overseen after the 1690s by the Board of Trade, a committee of the Privy
Council. As the Privy Council was a body of advisors to the Crown and not an
arm of Parliament this arrangement would appear to have preserved the
separation between the governments of the colonies and the government of
Britain. Where things became complicated was with the fact that the head of the
Board of Trade was often also the Secretary of State for the Colonies, a
cabinet-level position within the British government. Accordingly, colonial
affairs were treated in Britain as the responsibility of the government of the
day, and Parliament frequently passed laws intent on regulating colonial trade
in keeping with the overall administration of the British Empire. This became
particularly controversial in the 1760s when the government of Prime Minister
George Grenville attempted to levy a tax on stamped paper issued in the Thirteen
Colonies; because the line between the power of the British Government and the
power of the Crown had become blurred it was unclear who possessed legitimate
authority over the colonial governments. This uncertainty led to public disagreement,
vociferous debate, active resistance, harsh repression, and ultimately armed
revolution.
Having endorsed simplicity in
government as among the best ways to ensure transparency and stability, neither
of which the colonies enjoyed under the administration of the Crown, Paine
further pointed in the tenth through the twentieth paragraphs of Common Sense to specific elements of
Britain’s unwritten constitution that seemed to him calculated to create
inefficiency, confusion and conflict. Said constitution, he wrote, was composed
of three basic elements; led by a crowned individual, Britain was a monarchy;
partially governed by hereditary landowners, it was an aristocracy; daily
administered by elected representatives, it was a republic. The first two
elements Paine characterized as the residue of an earlier era, kept alive more
by tradition than logic, while the third was the product of more recent
historical events that was uneasily fitted to its surroundings. In theory these
three parts were supposed to check each-other’s power, though Paine considered
such a claim to be “farcical.” The monarchy in particular he singled out for
criticism, and presented a series of simple statements aimed at demonstrating
the contradictions inherent in the British attempt to fuse monarchical and
republican elements in a single government.
Believing that the House of
Commons had the ability to act as a check on the power of the monarch
presupposed two things, Paine argued. The first was that the monarch could not
be trusted to act in good faith at all times on the basis of their own
discretion. The logical conclusion was a general consensus that, as Paine put
it, “a thirst for absolute power is the natural disease of monarchy.” The
second assumption was that because the Commons was assigned the task of
checking, obstructing, or otherwise supervising the monarchy, it must have been
because they were, “wiser or more worthy of confidence than the crown.” Paine
did not seem inclined to disagree with either of these claims. Indeed, as aspects
of the so-called republican element of the British constitution I have no doubt
they fully warranted his endorsement. The problem – the cause of Paine’s claim
that the three-part constitution was a farce – arose from the monarch’s ability
to in turn check the power of the Commons by vetoing legislation. Such an
arrangement, he wrote, “supposes that the king is wiser than those whom is has
already supposed to be wiser than him. A mere absurdity!”